UNRAVELING AMBIGUITY AVERSION∗
Ilke Aydogan†
Lo¨ıc Berger‡
Valentina Bosetti§
Abstracto
We report the results of two experiments designed to better understand the
mechanisms driving decision-making under ambiguity. We elicit individual prefer-
ences over different sources of uncertainty, entailing different degrees of complexity,
from subjects with different sophistication levels. Nosotros mostramos que (1) ambiguity
aversion is robust to sophistication, but the strong relationship previously reported
between attitudes toward ambiguity and compound risk is not. (2) Ellsberg am-
biguity attitude can be partly explained by attitudes toward complexity for less
∗We thank Mohammed Abdellaoui, Aur´elien Baillon, Laure Cabantous, Thomas Ep-
por, Helena Hauser, Chen Li, Massimo Marinacci, Sujoy Mukerji, Vincent Th´eroude,
Uyanga Turmunkh, and Peter Wakker for helpful comments and suggestions. Nosotros también
thank seminar and conference participants at D-TEA, FUR, MUSEES, Bocconi Uni-
versity, Ghent University, and LMU for insightful comments and discussions. Somos
grateful to Hans-Joachim Zwiesler for the opportunity to run the experiment at ICA
2018 and thank the organizing committee for their help with the experiment. Nosotros
also thank Diana Valerio for her help with the laboratory experiment. This project
has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon Europe research and innova-
tion programme under grant agreement (No 101056891 CAPABLE), the Agence Na-
tionale de la Recherche (ANR-17-CE03-0008-01 INDUCED and ANR-21-CE03-0018
ENDURA), the Region Hauts-de-France (2021.00865 CLAM), and the I-SITE UNLE
(project IBEBACC). Logistic support from the Bocconi Experimental Laboratory for
the Social Sciences (BELSS) and from the Anthropo-Lab (ETHICS EA 7446) is kindly
acknowledged.
†IESEG School of Management, Univ. Lille, CNRS, UMR 9221 – LEM – Lille ´Economie
Management, F-59000 Lille, Francia; and iRisk Research Center on Risk and Uncertainty
(i.aydogan@ieseg.fr).
‡Corresponding author. Univ. Lille, CNRS, IESEG School of Management, UMR
9221 – LEM – Lille ´Economie Management, F-59000 Lille, Francia; iRisk Research Cen-
ter on Risk and Uncertainty; RFF-CMCC European Institute on Economics and the
Environment (EIEE), and Centro Euro-Mediterraneo sui Cambiamenti Climatici, Italia
(loic.berger@cnrs.fr). Phone: +33 320 545 892.
§Department of Economics and IGIER, Bocconi University, and RFF-CMCC Euro-
pean Institute on Economics and the Environment (EIEE), Centro Euro-Mediterraneo
sui Cambiamenti Climatici, Italia (valentina.bosetti@unibocconi.it).
1
yo
D
oh
w
norte
oh
a
d
mi
d
F
r
oh
metro
h
t
t
pag
:
/
/
d
i
r
mi
C
t
.
metro
i
t
.
mi
d
tu
/
r
mi
s
t
/
yo
a
r
t
i
C
mi
–
pag
d
F
/
d
oh
i
/
/
.
1
0
1
1
6
2
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
2
1
5
6
1
6
6
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
pag
d
.
F
b
y
gramo
tu
mi
s
t
t
oh
norte
0
7
S
mi
pag
mi
metro
b
mi
r
2
0
2
3
Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Internacional (CC POR 4.0) licencia.
sophisticated subjects only. En general, regardless of the subject’s sophistication level,
the main driver of Ellsberg ambiguity attitude is a specific treatment of unknown
probabilities.
Palabras clave: Ambiguity aversion, reduction of compound risk, model uncertainty, com-
plejidad
JEL Classification: C91-C93-D81
yo
D
oh
w
norte
oh
a
d
mi
d
F
r
oh
metro
h
t
t
pag
:
/
/
d
i
r
mi
C
t
.
metro
i
t
.
mi
d
tu
/
r
mi
s
t
/
yo
a
r
t
i
C
mi
–
pag
d
F
/
d
oh
i
/
.
/
1
0
1
1
6
2
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
2
1
5
6
1
6
6
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
pag
d
.
F
b
y
gramo
tu
mi
s
t
t
oh
norte
0
7
S
mi
pag
mi
metro
b
mi
r
2
0
2
3
2
Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Internacional (CC POR 4.0) licencia.
1
Introducción
For several decades, the standard way to make rational decisions under uncertainty has
been to follow Savage’s (1954) subjective expected utility (SEU) theory. En 1961, Ellsberg
proposed several experiments challenging canonical axioms of SEU. These experiments
have given rise to a vast literature studying the phenomenon of ambiguity aversion (es decir.,
the preference for known probabilities, or risk, over unknown probabilities, or ambiguity)
at both theoretical and empirical levels. Sin embargo, whether this deviation from SEU
constitutes an irrational response to uncertainty or not remains an open question (Gilboa
et al., 2009, 2010, 2012; Gilboa and Marinacci, 2013). As ambiguity is present and plays an
important role in most real-life decision problems,1 such a question is critical for normative
interpretations of ambiguity attitudes and for the use of ambiguity models in applications
with prescriptive purposes. Por eso, it has profound implications for policymaking (Berger
et al., 2021). Our goal, in this paper, is to clarify the extent to which ambiguity aversion
is tied to an arguable mistake, such as the failure to reduce compound lotteries, y
study its relationship with the decision-makers’ potential limitations or the complexity
of a situation.
We explore experimentally decision-making under uncertainty along three dimensions.
(1) The first dimension concerns the sources of uncertainty.2 We investigate attitudes
1Por ejemplo, in financial economics, Mukerji and Tallon (2001) show how ambiguity
aversion may lead to incompleteness of financial markets, while Easley and O’Hara (2009)
show how it can explain low participation in the stock market despite the potentially high
benefits. In the health domain, Berger et al. (2013) show that ambiguity aversion affects
treatment decisions. In climate change economics, Drouet et al. (2015) and Berger et al.
(2017) show how ambiguity aversion affects optimal emission policies.
2Sources of uncertainty are defined as “groups of events that are generated by the
same mechanism of uncertainty, which implies that they have similar characteristics”
(Abdellaoui et al., 2011, pag. 696).
3
yo
D
oh
w
norte
oh
a
d
mi
d
F
r
oh
metro
h
t
t
pag
:
/
/
d
i
r
mi
C
t
.
metro
i
t
.
mi
d
tu
/
r
mi
s
t
/
yo
a
r
t
i
C
mi
–
pag
d
F
/
d
oh
i
/
/
.
1
0
1
1
6
2
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
2
1
5
6
1
6
6
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
pag
d
.
F
b
y
gramo
tu
mi
s
t
t
oh
norte
0
7
S
mi
pag
mi
metro
b
mi
r
2
0
2
3
Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Internacional (CC POR 4.0) licencia.
toward different sources of risk (presented in simple or compound forms) and ambiguity
(presented in the form of model ambiguity `a la Marinacci (2015)3 or ambiguity `a la
Ellsberg (1961)). Under SEU, the distinction between these sources is irrelevant: todo
ambiguous sources are treated as risks through the assignment of subjective probabilities,
whereas compound risks are reduced to simple risks in accordance with the reduction
of compound lotteries axiom.
(2) The second dimension concerns the subjects’ level
of sophistication. We investigate the preferences of a unique pool of risk professionals
(working in insurance related jobs and possessing a high level of education in the fields of
matemáticas, Estadísticas, or actuarial science) and compare them to those of a convenience
sample of university students. Given their background and their training in dealing
with computationally complex problems requiring proficiency in probabilistic reasoning,
risk professionals can be considered as being more quantitatively “sophisticated” than
estudiantes. (3) Finalmente, the third dimension relates to the complexity of the problem. Por
proposing tasks with varying degrees of complexity within the same source, we are able
to isolate the role of complexity in decision-making under risk and ambiguity.
We elicit individual preferences using a two-color Ellsberg-type setting. The large
body of existing empirical literature using such a setting has so far highlighted two stylized
hechos:
SF1: Individuals are ambiguity averse.
SF2: There exists a strong relationship between attitudes towards ambiguity and com-
pound risk.
SF1 results from the many experiments that have formally tested Ellsberg’s (1961) idea,
typically using student subjects (L’Haridon et al., 2018; see also the reviews of Machina
3Model ambiguity arises when the decision-maker is not able to identify a single proba-
bility distribution (among a set of probability models) corresponding to the phenomenon
de interés (Hansen, 2014; Marinacci, 2015).
4
yo
D
oh
w
norte
oh
a
d
mi
d
F
r
oh
metro
h
t
t
pag
:
/
/
d
i
r
mi
C
t
.
metro
i
t
.
mi
d
tu
/
r
mi
s
t
/
yo
a
r
t
i
C
mi
–
pag
d
F
/
d
oh
i
/
/
.
1
0
1
1
6
2
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
2
1
5
6
1
6
6
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
pag
d
.
F
b
y
gramo
tu
mi
s
t
t
oh
norte
0
7
S
mi
pag
mi
metro
b
mi
r
2
0
2
3
Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Internacional (CC POR 4.0) licencia.
and Siniscalchi, 2014; Trautmann and van de Kuilen, 2015).4 It also typically generalizes
to alternative subject pools, including risk professionals (Cabantous, 2007; Cabantous
et al., 2011; Hogarth and Kunreuther, 1989). While ambiguity and compound risks have
distinct properties, SF2 has been put forward by Halevy (2007), who documented strong
similarities in attitudes towards Ellsberg ambiguity and compound risks among student
subjects. Based on his findings, Halevy wrote “The results suggest that failure to reduce
compound (objetivo) lotteries is the underlying factor of the Ellsberg paradox.” (halevy,
2007, pag. 532). Such findings have been replicated on other student samples (p.ej., Masticar
et al., 2017; Dean and Ortoleva, 2019; Gillen et al., 2019), and on a representative sample
of the U.S. población (Chapman et al., 2018). Whether explicitly or implicitly, SF2
has been invoked to challenge the normative status of ambiguity aversion. Específicamente,
if non-reduction of compound (o, more generally, of complex) risks is considered as a
mistake (possibly related to computational difficulties), and if the subjects making this
“mistake” are mainly those who are ambiguity non-neutral, there would be little room
for using ambiguity models for normative purposes.
Although results in line with SF1 and SF2 have consistently emerged from the lit-
erature, their relationship with the subjects’ level of sophistication has received little
attention so far. Exceptions are the studies of Chew et al. (2018), who investigate the
role of subjects’ level of comprehension for SF1; and Abdellaoui et al. (2015), and Berger
and Bosetti (2020), who report somewhat weaker relationships between ambiguity and
compound risk attitudes among engineering students and climate policymakers respec-
activamente. Además, the role of complexity as a factor contributing to explain SF1 and SF2
remains largely understudied, with the exceptions of Armantier and Treich (2016), y
Kov´aˇr´ık et al. (2016). Our paper attempts to fill these gaps by examining two research
4We note that ambiguity seeking is also common for ambiguous events with low like-
medios de vida. This local ambiguity seeking attitude is shown to be due to an ambiguity-
generated likelihood insensitivity (Dimmock et al., 2015). Our study focuses on proba-
bilities around 50% and does not consider this other component of ambiguity attitudes.
5
yo
D
oh
w
norte
oh
a
d
mi
d
F
r
oh
metro
h
t
t
pag
:
/
/
d
i
r
mi
C
t
.
metro
i
t
.
mi
d
tu
/
r
mi
s
t
/
yo
a
r
t
i
C
mi
–
pag
d
F
/
d
oh
i
/
/
.
1
0
1
1
6
2
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
2
1
5
6
1
6
6
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
pag
d
.
F
b
y
gramo
tu
mi
s
t
t
oh
norte
0
7
S
mi
pag
mi
metro
b
mi
r
2
0
2
3
Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Internacional (CC POR 4.0) licencia.
preguntas:
RQ1: Are SF1 & SF2 robust to sophistication?
RQ2: What are the main drivers of ambiguity attitude?
To answer these questions, we specifically targeted a sample of risk professionals, OMS
possess a high level of sophistication in probabilistic reasoning. To our knowledge, we are
the first to study the preferences of such a unique pool of subjects in an incentivized ex-
periment with a simple, context-free, design allowing us to make direct comparisons with
other subject pools. Although focusing on such a unique sample necessarily sacrifices
representativeness, it enables us to answer our first research question and to bring novel
insights on the role of sophistication. Our second research question aims at disentangling
the driving mechanisms of the Ellsberg paradox. Different explanations have been pro-
posed in the literature: Following theories that equate ambiguity to compound risk (p.ej.,
Segal, 1987; SEO, 2009), the driving factor of the Ellsberg paradox is the failure to reduce
compound risks.5 Along similar lines, some recent studies have suggested that ambiguity
aversion can be related to an aversion towards complex risks (p.ej., Armantier and Treich,
2016; Kov´aˇr´ık et al., 2016). Alternativamente, according to a variety of theoretical models
with normative underpinnings (see Gilboa and Marinacci, 2013, para una revisión), Ellsberg-
type behaviors are primarily driven by a specific attitude towards unknown probabilities.
In what follows, we analyze the effect of these factors to understand their respective roles
in explaining SF1 and SF2, and relate them to the subjects’ sophistication level.
2 experimentos
We report the results of two experiments. The data were collected in the context
of a broad research project investigating the layers of uncertainty (see Aydogan et al.,
5Segal (1987, pag. 179) wrote: “In other words, risk aversion and ambiguity aversion
are two sides of the same coin, and the rejection of the Ellsberg urn does not require a
new concept of ambiguity aversion, or a new concept of risk aversion.”
6
yo
D
oh
w
norte
oh
a
d
mi
d
F
r
oh
metro
h
t
t
pag
:
/
/
d
i
r
mi
C
t
.
metro
i
t
.
mi
d
tu
/
r
mi
s
t
/
yo
a
r
t
i
C
mi
–
pag
d
F
/
d
oh
i
/
/
.
1
0
1
1
6
2
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
2
1
5
6
1
6
6
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
pag
d
.
F
b
y
gramo
tu
mi
s
t
t
oh
norte
0
7
S
mi
pag
mi
metro
b
mi
r
2
0
2
3
Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Internacional (CC POR 4.0) licencia.
2023). Específicamente, Aydogan et al. (2023) proposed and experimentally tested the layer
hypothesis by comparing attitudes towards the layers of risk, model ambiguity, and model
misspecification. They reported behavioral differences across the three layers based on a
main experiment conducted with university students, which was supplemented by robust-
ness experiments conducted with different subject pools (including risk professionals). En
el estudio actual, we use a subset of the same data to address the distinct research ques-
tions RQ1 and RQ2.6 In particular, the current study focuses on the contrast between
two specific subject pools with distinct characteristics and documents new results on the
relationship between uncertainty, sophistication, and the level of complexity.
2.1 Samples
We consider two distinct samples. The main experiment in this study is an artefactual
field experiment run on a unique pool of risk professionals (actuaries). The control
experiment is a standard laboratory experiment with university students.
Actuaries at ICA We collected data from 84 risk professionals during the 31st Inter-
national Congress of Actuaries (ICA).7 The average age was around 40 y 44% del
subjects were female. The subjects were highly educated: 58 subjects (69%) reported
a master’s degree as the highest level of education completed and 18 subjects (21%) re-
ported a PhD degree. 46 subjects reported that their highest degree was obtained in a
field related to mathematics and statistics, mientras 17 subjects reported it related to actu-
6More specifically in the current study, we leave out the treatments involving model
misspecification and report on the standard Ellsberg treatment, which is different from
the Extended Ellsberg treatment reported in the main analysis of Aydogan et al. (2023).
7ICA is a conference organized by the International Actuarial Association every four
años. It gathers more than 2,500 actuaries, academics, and high-ranking representatives
from the international insurance and financial industry. The 31st congress was held from
Junio 4 a 8, 2018, in Berlin, Alemania.
7
yo
D
oh
w
norte
oh
a
d
mi
d
F
r
oh
metro
h
t
t
pag
:
/
/
d
i
r
mi
C
t
.
metro
i
t
.
mi
d
tu
/
r
mi
s
t
/
yo
a
r
t
i
C
mi
–
pag
d
F
/
d
oh
i
/
.
/
1
0
1
1
6
2
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
2
1
5
6
1
6
6
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
pag
d
.
F
b
y
gramo
tu
mi
s
t
t
oh
norte
0
7
S
mi
pag
mi
metro
b
mi
r
2
0
2
3
Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Internacional (CC POR 4.0) licencia.
arial sciences. The remaining subjects reported diplomas in physics (2), engineering (1),
finance (1), economics and management (3), or did not report anything (14). Finalmente, el
subjects had an average of 13 years of relevant work experience.
University students We collected data from 125 social science students at Bocconi
Universidad, Italia. At the time of the experiment, 80 de ellos (64%) were in a bachelor’s
program while 34 (27%) were in a master’s program, y el resto (9%) were in a PhD
programa. 42% of the subjects were female, and the average age was 20.5.
In what follows, we characterize sophistication by the background of the subjects.
En ese sentido, actuaries are considered as more “sophisticated” than students. Such a
distinction is justified on the ground that actuaries are experts in decision-making under
uncertainty and experienced risk evaluators, who are used to make decisions in situations
of ambiguity in their professional roles. They also possess a high training in statistics,
probability and decision theory. debería, sin embargo, be clear that different dimensions may
arguably contribute to making the pool of actuaries different than that of students. En
particular, the two samples differ in the following dimensions: (1) Curriculum: 79% del
actuaries possess a training in STEM (ciencia, tecnología, engineering, y matemáticas),
while the students are in social science programs; (2) Level of education: 90% del
actuaries reported to hold at least a master’s degree, while this is the case for only 9%
of the students; (3) Experience: actuaries reported an average 13 years of relevant work
experiencia, whereas most students had no work experience at all. Además, the age
difference between the two groups could be seen as a confounder to what precedes. Nosotros
report the results of a within-sample heterogeneity analysis in the Online Appendix.
2.2 Diseño
Sources of uncertainty We use a within subject design to study individual choices
under risk and ambiguity. The experiment entails betting on the color of a card drawn
from a deck in different situations. We consider the following four distinct sources of
uncertainty that are constructed in a two-color Ellsberg-type setting (see also Figure 1
8
yo
D
oh
w
norte
oh
a
d
mi
d
F
r
oh
metro
h
t
t
pag
:
/
/
d
i
r
mi
C
t
.
metro
i
t
.
mi
d
tu
/
r
mi
s
t
/
yo
a
r
t
i
C
mi
–
pag
d
F
/
d
oh
i
/
/
.
1
0
1
1
6
2
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
2
1
5
6
1
6
6
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
pag
d
.
F
b
y
gramo
tu
mi
s
t
t
oh
norte
0
7
S
mi
pag
mi
metro
b
mi
r
2
0
2
3
Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Internacional (CC POR 4.0) licencia.
(a)).
1. (R) Risk entails a deck that contains equal proportions of black and red cards.
2. (CR) Compound Risk entails, with equal probabilities, either a deck that contains
p% red and (1 − p)% black cards, or a deck that contains p% black and (1 − p)%
red cards.
3. (M A) Model Ambiguity entails, with unknown probabilities, either a deck that
contains p% red and (1 − p)% black cards, or a deck that contains p% black and
(1 − p)% red cards.
4. (mi) Ellsberg ambiguity entails a deck of 100 cards that contains an unknown pro-
portion of black and red cards.
yo
D
oh
w
norte
oh
a
d
mi
d
F
r
oh
metro
h
t
t
pag
:
/
/
d
i
r
mi
C
t
.
metro
i
t
.
mi
d
tu
/
r
mi
s
t
/
yo
a
r
t
i
C
mi
–
pag
d
F
/
d
oh
i
/
/
.
1
0
1
1
6
2
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
2
1
5
6
1
6
6
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
pag
d
.
F
b
y
gramo
tu
mi
s
t
t
oh
norte
0
7
S
mi
pag
mi
metro
b
mi
r
2
0
2
3
9
Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Internacional (CC POR 4.0) licencia.
(a) Illustration of the four sources of uncertainty (here p = 25 in CR and M A)
(b)
(C)
Cifra 1: Sources of uncertainty and their characteristics
yo
D
oh
w
norte
oh
a
d
mi
d
F
r
oh
metro
h
t
t
pag
:
/
/
d
i
r
mi
C
t
.
metro
i
t
.
mi
d
tu
/
r
mi
s
t
/
yo
a
r
t
i
C
mi
–
pag
d
F
/
d
oh
i
/
/
.
1
0
1
1
6
2
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
2
1
5
6
1
6
6
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
pag
d
.
F
b
y
gramo
tu
mi
s
t
t
oh
norte
0
7
S
mi
pag
mi
metro
b
mi
r
2
0
2
3
10
RiskAmbiguityRECRMANon compoundCompound1.a1.b1.cGlobal attitudes towards sourcesCR0MA0CR25MA25Less complexMore complex3223Attitudes CompoundriskModelambiguityReview of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Internacional (CC POR 4.0) licencia.
The sources R and CR are two sources of risk (known probabilities), mientras que el
sources M A and E are ambiguous (unknown probabilities). The sources CR and M A are
compounded as they explicitly entail two stages, with two potential deck compositions.
They differ from each other in the type of uncertainty they entail in the first stage.
Específicamente, the two possible deck compositions are unambiguously assigned an objective
50% probability under CR, whereas these probabilities are unknown in the case of M A.
On the basis of a symmetry argument, a 50% probability could be assigned to the two
possible deck compositions under M A, but these probabilities would then necessarily be
subjectively determined.8 E is the standard ambiguous source originally proposed by
Ellsberg (1961).
Complexity We consider a notion of complexity related to the number of stages of
uncertainty a situation features. Respectivamente, for each source CR and M A, we propose
two distinct cases that are characterized by different levels of complexity. In the first case,
we consider p = 0 so that the deck features a degenerate distribution: it contains either
100% black or 100% red cards. We denote the corresponding situations CR0 and M A0.9
This case is of minimal complexity: although the situation is presented in two stages, él
entails only one stage of uncertainty (as all the uncertainty stems from the first stage).
The second case considers p = 25, so that the deck contains either 25% rojo (y 75%
8In our experiment, symmetry in the prior distribution stems from the indifference
between betting on a red or black card. The symmetry condition can also be justified
on the grounds of a general symmetry of information argument: given the information
disponible, there is a priori no reason to believe that one composition deserves more weight
than another.
9In the literature, CR0 has also been used to study the hypothesis of time neutrality
(Segal, 1987, 1990; Dillenberger, 2010; Nielsen, 2020), es decir., the indifference between early
and late resolution of risk. It should be clear that the time dimension is not considered
in our experiment.
11
yo
D
oh
w
norte
oh
a
d
mi
d
F
r
oh
metro
h
t
t
pag
:
/
/
d
i
r
mi
C
t
.
metro
i
t
.
mi
d
tu
/
r
mi
s
t
/
yo
a
r
t
i
C
mi
–
pag
d
F
/
d
oh
i
/
.
/
1
0
1
1
6
2
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
2
1
5
6
1
6
6
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
pag
d
.
F
b
y
gramo
tu
mi
s
t
t
oh
norte
0
7
S
mi
pag
mi
metro
b
mi
r
2
0
2
3
Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Internacional (CC POR 4.0) licencia.
negro) cards or 25% negro (y 75% rojo) cards. We denote the corresponding situations
CR25 and M A25.10
Procedure Our experiments measure individual preferences over the situations R, CR0,
CR25, M A0, M A25, and E. For each of them, the subjects faced a bet on the color of a
card randomly drawn from a deck. For every bet, the winning color was determined by
the subjects themselves. We elicited the certainty equivalents (CEs) of the bets using a
choice-list design. We use the midpoint of an indifference interval implied by a switching
point as a proxy for the CE of a bet. In view of the stark income gap between risk pro-
fessionals and students (see Online Appendix), we adjusted the stakes offered to the two
groups by a factor of 10. Específicamente, bets yielded either e200 or e0 in the experiment
with actuaries and either e20 or e0 in the experiment with students. We used a standard
prior within-subject random incentive mechanism in the lab (es decir., all students were paid
based on one of their choices) but adopted a between-subject random incentive system in
the field (es decir., one-in-ten actuaries was paid) due to budgetary and logistical constraints.11
The details of the experimental procedures are provided in the Online Appendix.
10Note that our characterization of complexity can also be seen as referring to the
number of branches of a lottery. It is consistent with Chew et al. (2017, see footnote 20)
in the case of compound risk, and with the notion of complexity under simple risk, cual
is typically assessed by the number of different outcomes of the lottery (Sonsino et al.,
2002; Moffatt et al., 2015).
11Previous literature has reported no systematic difference between paying all subjects
or paying one-of-N (Beaud and Willinger 2015; Clot et al. 2018; Berlin et al. 2022). Nota
also that to further encourage risk professionals to reveal their preferences conditional on
being selected for payment, we carried out the between-subject randomization prior to the
experimento, thus enhancing the isolation assumption of Kahneman and Tversky (1979)
(see Johnson et al., 2021 for more discussion on the prior random incentive mechanisms).
Under the isolation assumption, the higher stakes offered to actuaries compensate for the
12
yo
D
oh
w
norte
oh
a
d
mi
d
F
r
oh
metro
h
t
t
pag
:
/
/
d
i
r
mi
C
t
.
metro
i
t
.
mi
d
tu
/
r
mi
s
t
/
yo
a
r
t
i
C
mi
–
pag
d
F
/
d
oh
i
/
.
/
1
0
1
1
6
2
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
2
1
5
6
1
6
6
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
pag
d
.
F
b
y
gramo
tu
mi
s
t
t
oh
norte
0
7
S
mi
pag
mi
metro
b
mi
r
2
0
2
3
Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Internacional (CC POR 4.0) licencia.
3 A relative premium measure
To examine attitudes toward the different sources of uncertainty, we introduce the
following premia measure relative to risk (R).
Definición 1. The relative premium ΠR,j is the difference between the CE of the bet on
R (CER) and the CE of the bet on j (CEj), expressed in % of the CE of the bet on the
most preferred situation:
ΠR,j ≡
CER − CEj
máximo {CER, CEj}
∀j ∈ {CR0, CR25, M A0, M A25, mi} .
(1)
Intuitivamente, two cases can be distinguished. If the individual is relatively more averse to
the uncertainty present in situation j, the preferred bet is the one on R, and the relative
premium represents the percentage of extra money that an individual would be ready to
sacrifice to avoid betting on j, relative to the value of the bet on R. Symmetrically, si
the preferred situation is j, the relative premium ΠR,j represents the extra money that
would be sacrificed to avoid betting on R, relative to the value of the bet on j. This index
possesses some desirable properties. Primero, ΠR,j is symmetric around zero across relatively
more or less averse preferences. Segundo, ΠR,j belongs to the interval [−1; 1], which also
makes it easy to interpret in terms of percentages. Por último, the normalization with respect
to the maximum CE allows more robust comparisons among subject pools by controlling
for differences in payoffs and subjects’ overall level of uncertainty attitudes.12
In the literature, ΠR,E has been commonly referred to as the Ellsberg-ambiguity pre-
mium (ver, p.ej., Berger, 2011; Maccheroni et al., 2013), and ΠR,CR as the compound risk
large income gap between risk professionals and students (see Online Appendix).
12In the Online Appendix, discutimos
some alternative measures
that have
been proposed in the literature, such as ΠR,j ≡ (CER − CEj)/CER or ΠR,j ≡
(CER − CEj)/(CER + CEj) (Sutter et al., 2013; Trautmann and van de Kuilen, 2015).
Our conclusions do not differ when using these alternative definitions.
13
yo
D
oh
w
norte
oh
a
d
mi
d
F
r
oh
metro
h
t
t
pag
:
/
/
d
i
r
mi
C
t
.
metro
i
t
.
mi
d
tu
/
r
mi
s
t
/
yo
a
r
t
i
C
mi
–
pag
d
F
/
d
oh
i
/
/
.
1
0
1
1
6
2
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
2
1
5
6
1
6
6
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
pag
d
.
F
b
y
gramo
tu
mi
s
t
t
oh
norte
0
7
S
mi
pag
mi
metro
b
mi
r
2
0
2
3
Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Internacional (CC POR 4.0) licencia.
premium (ver, p.ej., Abdellaoui et al., 2015).
En la misma vena, ΠR,M A represents the
model ambiguity premium. These premia are represented by the arrows 1.a-c in Figure
1(b). The relative premium can furthermore be used to measure the effects of complexity
and of a specific attitude toward unknown probabilities (in the first stage), as illustrated
by arrows 2 y 3 En figura 1(C). Específicamente, as the sources CR and M A both present
a relatively less and more complex case (es decir., one stage of uncertainty when p = 0 vs.
two stages of uncertainty when p = 25), the effect of complexity, within each source, poder
be examined by (ΠR,CR25 − ΠR,CR0) y (ΠR,M A25 − ΠR,M A0). These differences indicate
whether the compound risk or model ambiguity premia are larger in more complex cases
than in less complex ones. Similarmente, (ΠR,M A0 − ΠR,CR0) y (ΠR,M A25 − ΠR,CR25) gorra-
ture the effect of the distinct treatment of known and unknown probabilities in the first
stage within situations entailing the same degree of complexity.
4 Resultados
Our data consist of six choice lists per subject. Observations with multiple-switching,
reverse-switching, or no-switching patterns are not included in the analysis as they do
not provide clear measurements of the CEs.13 We do not detect any order effect on
tratos (see Online Appendix).
13The proportions of subjects affected by such inconsistencies in at least one of the
choice lists are 11.9% for actuaries (10 out of 84) y 10.4% for students (13 out of 125)
and do not differ across the two samples (two-sample Z-test of proportions, p=0.73).
Discarding four actuaries who show inconsistent patterns in all lists, suggesting a lack of
attention to the experiment, inconsistencies were present in 16 out of 480 liza (3.3%) para
actuaries and in 25 out of 750 liza (3.3%) for students. These proportions are notably
lower than what is typically observed in the literature (Yu et al., 2021).
14
yo
D
oh
w
norte
oh
a
d
mi
d
F
r
oh
metro
h
t
t
pag
:
/
/
d
i
r
mi
C
t
.
metro
i
t
.
mi
d
tu
/
r
mi
s
t
/
yo
a
r
t
i
C
mi
–
pag
d
F
/
d
oh
i
/
/
.
1
0
1
1
6
2
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
2
1
5
6
1
6
6
/
r
mi
s
t
_
a
_
0
1
3
5
8
pag
d
.
F
b
y
gramo
tu
mi
s
t
t
oh
norte
0
7
S
mi
pag
mi
metro
b
mi
r
2
0
2
3
Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Internacional (CC POR 4.0) licencia.
4.1 General attitudes toward different sources of uncertainty
Mesa 1 presents the mean relative premia. We observe that both groups of subjects
are comparable in terms of ambiguity premia, exhibiting aversion toward the sources M A
and E (t-tests, pag<0.001).14 This suggests that ambiguity aversion (SF1) is robust to the subjects’ level of sophistication. Regarding the source CR, the average relative premium for CR25 is positive for students (p<0.001), indicating aversion toward compound risk, but we cannot reject the null hypothesis that ΠR,CR25 = 0 for actuaries (t-test, p=0.03 but p=0.17 after Bonferroni correction15). The difference between actuaries and students is particularly marked for this premium (t-test, p<0.001). In contrast, the average relative premium for the less complex case CR0 does not differ from zero for both groups (t-test, p=0.59 for actuaries, and p=0.55 for students). l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . e d u / r e s t / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / . / 1 0 1 1 6 2 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 2 1 5 6 1 6 6 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 14Testing multiple hypotheses (e.g., testing H0 : ΠR,j = 0 for all j ∈ {CR0, CR25, M A0, M A25, E}) may require Bonferroni corrections. To allow for direct comparisons with previous literature, we report the original p-values, together with Bon- ferroni corrections when these affect the results. 15The minimum detectable difference from zero mean premium for 5% level of signifi- cance (with Bonferroni correction) and a power of 90% is 0.043. 15 Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0) license. Table 1: Average premia relative to risk Actuaries Students ΠR,CR0 ΠR,CR25 -0.007 (0.0127) 0.023∗ (0.0108) 0.010 (0.0171) 0.136∗∗∗ (0.0216) Two-sample tests (p-value) 0.472 <0.001 ΠR,M A0 ΠR,M A25 ΠR,E Notes: Standard errors in parentheses. The tests are based on two-sided t-tests. 0.121∗∗∗ (0.0324) 0.106∗∗∗ (0.0227) 0.190∗∗∗ (0.0316) 0.130∗∗∗ (0.0219) 0.181∗∗∗ (0.0227) 0.191∗∗∗ (0.0249) 0.814 0.027 0.982 ∗∗∗ significant at 0.001, ∗∗ significant at 0.01, ∗ significant at 0.05. Significance stars are based on p-values before Bonferroni correction. Values that are significant at 0.05 after Bonferroni correction are bolded. l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . e d u / r e s t / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / / . 1 0 1 1 6 2 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 2 1 5 6 1 6 6 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 16 Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0) license. 4.2 The relationship between ambiguity and compound risk at- titudes Following the existing literature, we investigate the relationship between attitudes towards ambiguity and compound risk within our two subject pools and test the robust- ness of SF2 to sophistication. Table 2 reports the Pearson correlation coefficients between compound risk premia and ambiguity premia.16 In line with SF2, we observe a significant correlation between attitudes toward ambiguity and compound risk for students (except between ΠR,CR0 and ΠR,E, p=0.475). However, such a relationship is absent in the case of actuaries.17 l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . e d u / r e s t / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / . / 1 0 1 1 6 2 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 2 1 5 6 1 6 6 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 16The same conclusions are obtained with Spearman rank correlations, which measure monotonic –rather than linear– relationships between premia (see Online Appendix). 17We also analyzed correlations based on the method of obviously related instrumen- tal variables (ORIV) developed by Gillen et al. (2019) to correct for measurement errors. ORIV uses an instrumental variable approach to compute correlations when there are multiple measurements of behavioral variables. We used ORIV in our data by using multiple elicitations of preferences under compound risk and model ambigu- ity (i.e., with p = 0 and p = 25). We observe that, although the correlations be- tween compound risk and ambiguity using ORIV are consistently high for students: corr(ΠR,CR, ΠR,M A)=0.988 and corr(ΠR,CR, ΠR,E)=0.916, they remain remarkably low for actuaries: corr(ΠR,CR, ΠR,M A)=0.369 and corr(ΠR,CR, ΠR,E)=0.057. 17 Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0) license. Table 2: Pearson correlations between compound risk and ambiguity pre- mia Actuaries Students ΠR,M A0 ΠR,M A25 ΠR,E ΠR,M A0 ΠR,M A25 ΠR,E 0.169 0.135 -0.033 -0.078 ΠR,CR0 ΠR,CR25 Notes: ∗∗∗ significant at 0.001, ∗∗ significant at 0.01, ∗ significant at 0.05. Significance stars are based on p-values before Bonferroni correction. Values that are significant at 0.05 after Bonferroni correction are bolded. 0.315∗∗∗ 0.344∗∗∗ 0.407∗∗∗ 0.652∗∗∗ 0.475∗∗∗ ΠR,CR0 ΠR,CR25 0.067 0.107 0.109 l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . e d u / r e s t / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / / . 1 0 1 1 6 2 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 2 1 5 6 1 6 6 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 18 Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0) license. Next, we examine the links between ambiguity neutrality and reduction of compound risk. We adopted a comprehensive definition of ambiguity neutrality according to which a subject is considered as ambiguity neutral if ΠR,E = ΠR,M A0 = ΠR,M A25 = 0.18 Similarly, a subject is said to be reducing compound risk if ΠR,CR0 = ΠR,CR25 = 0. The proportion of ambiguity non-neutrality among subjects who do not reduce com- pound risk is 95% (=20/21) for actuaries and 94% (=77/82) for students. These propor- tions, which are in line with the literature, suggest that non-reduction of CR is sufficient for ambiguity non-neutrality, irrespective of the subjects’ sophistication level. Turning to necessity, we find that 80% (=77/96) of ambiguity non-neutral students are also not re- ducing CR. However, this proportion is 57% (=20/35) for actuaries, which is significantly less than for students (two-sample test of proportions, p=0.008). This result indicates that, although compound risk non-reduction appears to be also necessary for ambiguity non-neutrality when less sophisticated subjects are considered, this is not the case for more sophisticated ones. Overall, this first set of results enables us to answer RQ1. Result 1 (a) Ambiguity aversion is robust to the subjects’ sophistication level, but (b) the strong relationship between attitudes toward ambiguity and compound risk is not. 4.3 Complexity and ambiguity We now focus on compound sources to examine the effects of complexity and ambiguity in different subject pools. For this, we run a regression analysis with random effects at individual level, where the relative premia ΠR,j for j ∈ {CR0, CR25, M A0, M A25} are regressed on a dummy for complexity (taking value 1 if j ∈ {CR25, M A25}), a dummy for the presence of ambiguity (taking value 1 if j ∈ {M A0, M A25}), and their interaction. The baseline is the behavior in a compound risk situation with minimal complexity. To test the effect of sophistication, we run a regression by pooling data from the two samples and using a dummy for actuaries. 18Our conclusions are robust to the use of alternative definitions of ambiguity neutrality under M A and E separately (see Online Appendix). 19 l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . e d u / r e s t / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / . / 1 0 1 1 6 2 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 2 1 5 6 1 6 6 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0) license. Table 3 reports the results. We observe positive coefficients for complexity and model ambiguity, indicating that the relative premia are higher when the situation is more complex or does not entail objective probabilities, in comparison to the less complex situation with objective probabilities (i.e., CR0). Therefore, both students and actuaries can be said to be averse to complexity and unknown probabilities in the first-stage. However, the effect of complexity is significantly lower among actuaries than among students, although there is no difference between the two groups regarding the effect of unknown probabilities. We also observe a negative interaction between the variables, suggesting that the effect of complexity is less pronounced in the presence of model ambiguity. This interaction is significant for students but not for actuaries. l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . e d u / r e s t / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / . / 1 0 1 1 6 2 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 2 1 5 6 1 6 6 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 20 Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0) license. Table 3: Random Effects Regressions of Relative Premia Complexity Model ambiguity Complexity × Model ambiguity Constant Actuaries Students 0.031∗ (0.015) 0.128∗∗∗ (0.033) -0.046 (0.031) 0.123∗∗∗ (0.023) 0.120∗∗∗ (0.023) -0.075∗∗ (0.026) -0.006 (0.013) 299 0.010 (0.017) 471 Effect of sophistication (pooled data) -0.092∗∗∗ (0.027) 0.008 (0.040) 0.028 (0.040) -0.016 (0.021) 770 Observations Notes: Cluster-robust standard errors in parentheses. ∗∗∗ significant at 0.001, ∗∗ significant at 0.01, ∗ significant at 0.05. Similar results are obtained when controling for age, gender, income, and education (see Online Appendix). l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . e d u / r e s t / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / . / 1 0 1 1 6 2 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 2 1 5 6 1 6 6 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 21 Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0) license. 4.4 Explaining Ellsberg ambiguity Based on what precedes, we now investigate the roles of attitudes toward complex- ity and unknown probabilities, together with the failure of the reduction principle in explaining Ellsberg-ambiguity attitude. We use the following OLS regression: E-AM Bi = β0 + β1COM P Xi + β2U N KN OW Ni + β3REDi + εi, (2) where Ellsberg ambiguity attitude (E-AM B) for subject i is computed by ΠR,E. At- titudes toward complexity and unknown probabilities (COM P X and U N KN OW N , respectively) are both measured with respect to ΠR,CR0 to isolate their pure effects and avoid interactions between them. Specifically, complexity attitude is captured by (ΠR,CR25 − ΠR,CR0), which computes the difference between the compound risk premia under different degrees of complexity.19 Attitude toward unknown probabilities is mea- sured by (ΠR,M A0 − ΠR,CR0), which captures the difference in relative premia between two compound situations presenting the same degree of complexity, but different type of probabilities in their first stage.20 Finally, the measure of reduction (RED) is based on ΠR,CR0: As CR0 is arguably the most easily reducible compound risk situation, its non-reduction shows a clear failure of the reduction principle (rather than a failure to deal with complexity). The dummy for (non-) reduction takes 1 if ΠR,CR0 (cid:54)= 0 and 0 otherwise. Table 4 reports the results of the regressions. We find that attitude toward un- known probabilities has a positive and significant impact for both actuaries and stu- 19Note that the alternative, which is to use (ΠR,M A25 − ΠR,M A0), could be confounded by ambiguity attitudes because M A0 may also be seen as being more ambiguous than M A25 due to a larger spread of first stage probabilities (see Jewitt and Mukerji, 2017; Berger, 2022). 20The alternative, which is to use (ΠR,M A25 − ΠR,CR25) could be confounded by risk attitudes because of the presence of risk in the second stage (see the discussion in Berger and Bosetti, 2020). 22 l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . e d u / r e s t / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / / . 1 0 1 1 6 2 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 2 1 5 6 1 6 6 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0) license. dents. The magnitudes of the coefficients indicate that one percentage point increase in (ΠR,M A0 − ΠR,CR0) leads to 0.74 percentage points increase in ΠR,E for actuaries, and to 0.43 percentage points increase for students. The difference in this coefficient between the two groups is significant (p = 0.03), indicating a stronger effect of attitude toward unknown probabilities for actuaries. In contrast, complexity attitude has a positive and significant impact for students only. The difference in the magnitude of the coefficients between the groups suggests that the effect of complexity is also more pronounced for students (p=0.04). Finally, the positive coefficients of the reduction variable suggest that failure of the reduction principle increases the ambiguity premium, although the coeffi- cients are neither significant nor different in the two groups. Overall, this second set of results enables us to answer RQ2. Result 2: (a) For both actuaries and students, the main driver of Ellsberg-ambiguity attitude is a specific treatment of unknown probabilities. (b) A specific attitude toward complexity is found to play a significant role in explaining Ellsberg-ambiguity attitude for students only. l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . e d u / r e s t / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / / . 1 0 1 1 6 2 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 2 1 5 6 1 6 6 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 23 Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0) license. Table 4: OLS Regressions of Ellsberg Ambiguity Premium COM P X U N KN OW N RED Constant Actuaries Students -0.170 (0.167) 0.735∗∗∗ (0.091) 0.137 (0.074) 0.079∗∗ (0.026) 0.253∗ (0.116) 0.434∗∗∗ (0.106) 0.036 (0.048) 0.091∗∗∗ (0.024) Difference between groups (pooled data) -0.423∗ (0.203) 0.302∗ (0.140) 0.101 (0.088) -0.012 (0.036) Observations Notes: Robust standard errors in parentheses, ∗∗∗ significant at 0.001, ∗∗ signif- 188 114 74 icant at 0.01, ∗ significant at 0.05. Simlar results are obtained when controling for age, gender, income, and education. l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . e d u / r e s t / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / . / 1 0 1 1 6 2 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 2 1 5 6 1 6 6 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 24 Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0) license. 5 Concluding remarks Decisions made by unusual subject pools, such as climate policymakers (Berger and Bosetti, 2020), professional traders (Fox et al., 1996), professional chess players (Levitt et al., 2011), or golf players (Pope and Schweitzer, 2011) have been the focus of stud- ies trying to explain important behavioral phenomena. Following this line of research, we focus on a unique pool of risk professionals to re-examine two stylized facts about ambiguity attitudes, which have emerged in the literature. Because these professionals routinely price risk and uncertainty at work, their occupational practice makes them of special interest for studying decision-making under uncertainty. Our results show that this selected group of subjects is as much affected by ambi- guity as a standard pool of university students. However, attitudes towards ambiguity and compound risk are less closely related for risk professionals than for students. In particular, compound risk non-reduction is found sufficient but not necessary for am- biguity non-neutrality for these more sophisticated subjects. We argue that attitudes toward complexity may explain these findings. Indeed, if ambiguity is viewed as a com- pound source of uncertainty, or presented as such (as in model ambiguity situations), non-reduction of compound risk can be sufficient for ambiguity non-neutrality. On the other hand, if complexity makes compound risk situations being perceived as ambiguous by some subjects, those who are ambiguity non-neutral will also exhibit compound risk non-reduction (and hence the necessity). Interestingly, this effect is significantly weaker for more sophisticated subjects, who are less affected by the complexity of a situation. Consistent with this interpretation, we observe that a non-negligible proportion of ambi- guity non-neutral actuaries do actually reduce compound risk. The paper closest to ours is Abdellaoui et al. (2015), who compared two student samples differing in their training (engineering vs. non-engineering fields). While they also report a somewhat weaker link between compound risk and ambiguity for more quantitatively sophisticated students, the differences they find between their two student samples are not as stark as those between students and actuaries. By studying a pool of 25 l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . e d u / r e s t / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / . / 1 0 1 1 6 2 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 2 1 5 6 1 6 6 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0) license. risk professionals, whose contrast with students is more extreme, our study may be seen as more revealing for the role of sophistication in decision-making. Yet we also note that differences in sophistication might exist within the populations studied. An additional analysis of our data indeed indicates some heterogeneity among students but not among risk professionals (for the details, see Online Appendix). For example, undergraduate students are found to be more affected by complexity than graduate ones, whereas work experience (or age) is not found to play any role among actuaries. We argue that our findings may have important implications for different ambiguity models. Overall, by suggesting that ambiguity aversion is mainly driven by a genuine preference for known probabilities over unknown ones, but not necessarily by an inabil- ity/aversion to deal with the compoundness or complexity of a situation, the results we report in this paper are more consistent with the predictions of ambiguity theories with normative underpinnings. Thus, they leave room for using ambiguity models in applications with prescriptive purposes. l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . e d u / r e s t / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / . / 1 0 1 1 6 2 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 2 1 5 6 1 6 6 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 26 Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0) license. References Abdellaoui, Mohammed, Aur´elien Baillon, Laetitia Placido, and Peter P Wakker (2011) “The rich domain of uncertainty: Source functions and their experimental implemen- tation,” The American Economic Review, 101 (2), 695–723. Abdellaoui, Mohammed, Peter Klibanoff, and Lætitia Placido (2015) “Experiments on Compound Risk in Relation to Simple Risk and to Ambiguity,” Management Science, 61 (6), 1306–1322. Armantier, Olivier and Nicolas Treich (2016) “The Rich Domain of Risk,” Management Science, 62, 1954–1969. Aydogan, Ilke, Lo¨ıc Berger, Valentina Bosetti, and Ning Liu (2023) “Three Layers of Uncertainty,” Journal of the European Economic Association. Beaud, Mickael and Marc Willinger (2015) “Are people risk vulnerable?” Management Science, 61 (3), 624–636. Berger, Lo¨ıc (2011) “Smooth Ambiguity Aversion in the Small and in the Large,” Working Papers ECARES 2011-020, ULB – Universit´e libre de Bruxelles. Berger, Lo¨ıc (2022) “What is Partial Ambiguity?” Economics and Philosophy, 38 (2), 206–220. Berger, Lo¨ıc, Nicolas Berger, Valentina Bosetti, Itzhak Gilboa, Lars Peter Hansen, Christopher Jarvis, Massimo Marinacci, and Richard D. Smith (2021) “Rational Pol- icymaking during a Pandemic,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, 118 (4), e2012704118. 27 l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . e d u / r e s t / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / . / 1 0 1 1 6 2 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 2 1 5 6 1 6 6 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0) license. Berger, Lo¨ıc, Han Bleichrodt, and Louis Eeckhoudt (2013) “Treatment decisions under ambiguity,” Journal of Health Economics, 32 (3), 559–569. Berger, Lo¨ıc and Valentina Bosetti (2020) “Are Policymakers Ambiguity Averse?” The Economic Journal, 130, 331–355. Berger, Lo¨ıc, Johannes Emmerling, and Massimo Tavoni (2017) “Managing Catastrophic Climate Risks Under Model Uncertainty Aversion,” Management Science, 63 (3), 749– 765. Berlin, Noemie, Emmanuel Kemel, Vincent Lenglin, and Antoine Nebout-Javal (2022) “A convenient truth : between-subject random incentives and preferences towards risk and time,” mimeo. Cabantous, Laure (2007) “Ambiguity aversion in the field of insurance: Insurers’ attitude to imprecise and conflicting probability estimates,” Theory and Decision, 62 (3), 219– 240. Cabantous, Laure, Denis Hilton, Howard Kunreuther, and Erwann Michel-Kerjan (2011) “Is imprecise knowledge better than conflicting expertise? Evidence from insurers’ decisions in the United States,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 42 (3), 211–232. Chapman, Jonathan, Mark Dean, Pietro Ortoleva, Erik Snowberg, and Colin Camerer (2018) “Econographics,”Technical report, National Bureau of Economic Research. Chew, Soo Hong, B. Miao, and S. Zhong (2017) “Partial Ambiguity,” Econometrica, 85 (4), 1239–1260. Chew, Soo Hong, Mark Ratchford, and Jacob S. Sagi (2018) “You Need to Recognise Ambiguity to Avoid It,” The Economic Journal, 128 (614), 2480–2506. 28 l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . e d u / r e s t / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / . / 1 0 1 1 6 2 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 2 1 5 6 1 6 6 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0) license. Clot, Sophie, Gilles Grolleau, and Lisette Ibanez (2018) “Shall we pay all? An experi- mental test of Random Incentivized Systems,” Journal of Behavioral and Experimental Economics, 73, 93–98. Dean, Mark and Pietro Ortoleva (2019) “The empirical relationship between nonstan- dard economic behaviors,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 116 (33), 16262–16267. Dillenberger, David (2010) “Preferences for one-shot resolution of uncertainty and Allais- type behavior,” Econometrica, 78 (6), 1973–2004. Dimmock, Stephen G, Roy Kouwenberg, and Peter P Wakker (2015) “Ambiguity Atti- tudes in a Large Representative Sample,” Management Science, null. Drouet, Laurent, Valentina Bosetti, and Massimo Tavoni (2015) “Selection of Climate Policies under the uncertainties in the Fifth Assessment Report of the IPCC,” Nature Climate Change, 5, 937–940. Easley, David and Maureen O’Hara (2009) “Ambiguity and nonparticipation: The role of regulation,” The Review of Financial Studies, 22 (5), 1817–1843. Ellsberg, Daniel (1961) “Risk, ambiguity, and the Savage axioms,” The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 75, 643–669. Fox, Craig R, Brett A Rogers, and Amos Tversky (1996) “Options traders exhibit sub- additive decision weights,” Journal of Risk and uncertainty, 13 (1), 5–17. Gilboa, Itzhak, Fabio Maccheroni, Massimo Marinacci, and David Schmeidler (2010) “Objective and subjective rationality in a multiple prior model,” Econometrica, 78 (2), 755–770. 29 l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . e d u / r e s t / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / / . 1 0 1 1 6 2 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 2 1 5 6 1 6 6 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0) license. Gilboa, Itzhak and Massimo Marinacci (2013) “Ambiguity and the Bayesian paradigm,” in Advances in Economics and Econometrics: Theory and Applications, Tenth World Congress of the Econometric Society.: D. Acemoglu, M. Arellano, and E. Dekel (Eds.). New York: Cambridge University Press. Gilboa, Itzhak, Andrew Postlewaite, and David Schmeidler (2009) “Is it always rational to satisfy Savage’s axioms?” Economics and Philosophy, 25 (3), 285–296. (2012) “Rationality of belief or: why Savage’s axioms are neither necessary nor sufficient for rationality,” Synthese, 187 (1), 11–31. Gillen, Ben, Erik Snowberg, and Leeat Yariv (2019) “Experimenting with measurement error: Techniques with applications to the caltech cohort study,” Journal of Political Economy, 127 (4), 1826–1863. Halevy, Yoram (2007) “Ellsberg revisited: An experimental study,” Econometrica, 75 (2), 503–536. Hansen, Lars Peter (2014) “Nobel Lecture: Uncertainty Outside and Inside Economic Models,” Journal of Political Economy, 122 (5), 945–987. Hogarth, Robin M and Howard Kunreuther (1989) “Risk, ambiguity, and insurance,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 2 (1), 5–35. Jewitt, Ian and Sujoy Mukerji (2017) “Ordering Ambiguous Acts,” Journal of Economic Theory, 171, 213–267. Johnson, Cathleen, Aur´elien Baillon, Han Bleichrodt, Zhihua Li, Dennie Van Dolder, and Peter P Wakker (2021) “Prince: An improved method for measuring incentivized preferences,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 1–28. 30 l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . e d u / r e s t / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / . / 1 0 1 1 6 2 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 2 1 5 6 1 6 6 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0) license. Kahneman, Daniel and Amos Tversky (1979) “Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk,” Econometrica, 47 (2), 363–391. Kov´aˇr´ık, Jarom´ır, Dan Levin, and Tao Wang (2016) “Ellsberg paradox: Ambiguity and complexity aversions compared,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 52 (1), 47–64. Levitt, Steven D, John A List, and Sally E Sadoff (2011) “Checkmate: Exploring back- ward induction among chess players,” American Economic Review, 101 (2), 975–90. L’Haridon, Olivier, Ferdinand M Vieider, Diego Aycinena, Agustinus Bandur, Alexis Belianin, Lubomir Cingl, Amit Kothiyal, and Peter Martinsson (2018) “Off the charts: Massive unexplained heterogeneity in a global study of ambiguity attitudes,” Review of Economics and Statistics, 100 (4), 664–677. Maccheroni, Fabio, Massimo Marinacci, and Doriana Ruffino (2013) “Alpha as Ambigu- ity: Robust Mean-Variance Portfolio Analysis,” Econometrica, 81 (3), 1075–1113. Machina, Mark J and Marciano Siniscalchi (2014) “Ambiguity and ambiguity aversion,” in Handbook of the Economics of Risk and Uncertainty, 1, 729–807: Elsevier. Marinacci, Massimo (2015) “Model Uncertainty,” Journal of the European Economic Association, 13 (6), 1022–1100. Moffatt, Peter G, Stefania Sitzia, and Daniel John Zizzo (2015) “Heterogeneity in pref- erences towards complexity,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 51 (2), 147–170. Mukerji, Sujoy and Jean-Marc Tallon (2001) “Ambiguity aversion and incompleteness of financial markets,” The Review of Economic Studies, 68 (4), 883–904. Nielsen, Kirby (2020) “Preferences for the resolution of uncertainty and the timing of information,” Journal of Economic Theory, 189, 105090. 31 l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . e d u / r e s t / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / / . 1 0 1 1 6 2 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 2 1 5 6 1 6 6 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0) license. Pope, Devin G and Maurice E Schweitzer (2011) “Is Tiger Woods loss averse? Persistent bias in the face of experience, competition, and high stakes,” American Economic Review, 101 (1), 129–57. Savage, Leonard J (1954) The Foundations of Statistics, New York: J. Wiley, Second revised edition, 1972. Segal, Uzi (1987) “The Ellsberg paradox and risk aversion: An anticipated utility ap- proach,” International Economic Review, 175–202. (1990) “Two-stage lotteries without the reduction axiom,” Econometrica, 349– 377. Seo, Kyoungwon (2009) “Ambiguity and Second-Order Belief,” Econometrica, 77 (5), 1575–1605. Sonsino, Doron, Uri Benzion, and Galit Mador (2002) “The complexity effects on choice with uncertainty–Experimental evidence,” The Economic Journal, 112 (482), 936–965. Sutter, Matthias, Martin G Kocher, Daniela Gl¨atzle-R¨utzler, and Stefan T Trautmann (2013) “Impatience and uncertainty: Experimental decisions predict adolescents’ field behavior,” American Economic Review, 103 (1), 510–31. Trautmann, Stefan T. and Gijs van de Kuilen (2015) Ambiguity Attitudes, Chap. 3, 89– 116: The Wiley Blackwell Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making, John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Yu, Chi Wai, Y Jane Zhang, and Sharon Xuejing Zuo (2021) “Multiple switching and data quality in the multiple price list,” Review of Economics and Statistics, 103 (1), 136–150. 32 l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . e d u / r e s t / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / / . 1 0 1 1 6 2 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 2 1 5 6 1 6 6 / r e s t _ a _ 0 1 3 5 8 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 Review of Economics and Statistics Just Accepted MS. https://doi.org/10.1162/rest_a_01358 © 2023 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0) license.