REPORT

REPORT

Does Local Coherence Lead to Targeted
Regressions and Illusions of Grammaticality?

Dario Paape1

, Shravan Vasishth1, and Ralf Engbert2

1Department of Linguistics, University of Potsdam, Potsdam, Allemagne
2Département de psychologie, University of Potsdam, Potsdam, Allemagne

un accès ouvert

journal

ABSTRAIT

Mots clés: local coherence, eye tracking, grammaticality judgments, targeted regressions

je

D
o
w
n
o
un
d
e
d

F
r
o
m
h

t
t

p

:
/
/

d
je
r
e
c
t
.

m

je
t
.

/

e
d
toi
o
p
m

je
/

je

un
r
t
je
c
e

p
d

F
/

d
o

je
/

je

/

/

.

1
0
1
1
6
2
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
1
9
2
8
2
5
7
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
p
d

/

.

je

Local coherence effects arise when the human sentence processor is temporarily misled by a
locally grammatical but globally ungrammatical analysis (The coach smiled at the player
tossed a frisbee by the opposing team). It has been suggested that such effects occur either
because sentence processing occurs in a bottom-up, self-organized manner rather than
under constant grammatical supervision, or because local coherence can disrupt processing
due to readers maintaining uncertainty about previous input. We report the results of an
eye-tracking study in which subjects read German grammatical and ungrammatical sentences
that either contained a locally coherent substring or not and gave binary grammaticality
judgments. In our data, local coherence affected on-line processing immediately at the point
of the manipulation. There was, cependant, no indication that local coherence led to illusions
of grammaticality (a prediction of self-organization), and only weak, inconclusive support
for local coherence leading to targeted regressions to critical context words (a prediction of
the uncertain-input approach). We discuss implications for self-organized and noisy-channel
models of local coherence.

F

b
oui
g
toi
e
s
t

t

o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3

INTRODUCTION

Ever since their discovery by Tabor et al. (2004), local coherence effects have posed an inter-
esting conundrum for standard theories of human sentence processing. The sentence in (1un)
has only one correct parse, in which the noun phrase the player is modified by a reduced
relative clause and the agent of the verb toss remains unrealized. The exact same parse is
available for sentence (1b), where the relative clause is unreduced, et pour (1c), which re-
places the passive participle with that of a semantically similar verb, throw.

(1) un. The coach smiled at the player tossed a frisbee by the opposing team.

b. The coach smiled at the player who was tossed a frisbee by the opposing team.
c. The coach smiled at the player thrown a frisbee by the opposing team.

In a self-paced reading experiment Tabor et al. (2004) found that the words tossed/thrown
a frisbee took longer to process in (1un) compared to (1b) et (1c). They replicated the effect in

Citation: Paape, D., Vasishth, S., &
Engbert, R.. (2021). Does Local
Coherence Lead to Targeted
Regressions and Illusions of
Grammaticality? Open Mind:
Discoveries in Cognitive Science,
5, 42–58. https://doi.org
/10.1162/opmi_a_00041

EST CE QUE JE:
https://doi.org/10.1162/opmi_a_00041

Supplemental Materials:
https://osf.io/ersxn; https://osf.io/f6ntk

Reçu: 12 Juin 2020
Accepté: 25 Avril 2021

Intérêts concurrents: The authors
declare no conflict of interest.

Auteur correspondant:
Dario Paape
paape@uni-potsdam.de

droits d'auteur: © 2021
Massachusetts Institute of Technology
Publié sous Creative Commons
Attribution 4.0 International
(CC PAR 4.0) Licence

La presse du MIT

Local Coherence and Ungrammaticality

Paape, Vasishth, Engbert

a second self-paced reading study and in a grammaticality judgment study, où (1un) était
more likely to be rejected than (1b) et (1c). This pattern is consistent with the idea that in
(1un), the human sentence processor is led astray due to the substring the player tossed a
frisbee being a possible active main clause, even though it appears at a position in the
sentence where such an analysis is ruled out by grammar. Tabor et al. (2004) argue that such
local coherence effects may be best explained by parsing models that relax the principle of
grammatical self-consistency, which requires that the parser only considers globally legal
analyses at every point during the parse. A class of models that do not assume self-
consistency are self-organized parsing models such as SOPARSE (Tabor & Hutchins, 2004)
and Unification Space ( Vosse & Kempen, 2000). In these models, lexical items bring with
them small pieces of syntactic structure that may freely combine at any point during pro-
cessing and attempt to form a globally well-formed tree structure (Forgeron, 2018; Smith et al.,
2018; Villata & Franck, 2020). If multiple locally well-formed attachments compete with each
other, processing difficulty arises. Slowed reading in locally coherent structures is naturally
accounted for by this kind of model as the underlined local analysis in (1un) competes with the
globally correct analysis. If the conflict between the two cannot be resolved, parsing failure
may result.

An entirely different explanation of local coherence effects, the noisy-channel model, était
proposed by Levy (2008b) and tested by Levy et al. (2009). The model rests on the assumption
that readers maintain some uncertainty about the words they have read, and may consider the
possibility that they did not read the word at in (1un), but rather the word and or the word as,
or that at may have been a typo. The main intuition is that readers may change their assump-
tions about the identity of previously read words when subsequent input does not easily fit
with the current parse. Par exemple, dans (1un), changing at to as only requires substitution of one
letter and results in the possibility of a high-probability alternative parse in which tossed is
analyzed as an active verb (The coach smiled as the player tossed a frisbee). Levy (2008b)
assumes that large changes in the reader’s belief about the previous input result in slowed
processing and, if possible, in regressive saccades, due to lingering uncertainty about the ac-
tual identity of the critical word at. Given that the alternative parse is not available in (1b, 1c),
no revision of beliefs is triggered at tossed/thrown, and the difference between conditions is
thus accounted for.

Given the assumed link between uncertainty about previous input and overt regressions in
the noisy-channel model, data from eye tracking during reading are potentially informative
when it comes to dissociating the two proposed explanations.1 Research on temporarily am-
biguous garden-path sentences has yielded some evidence that readers engage in targeted re-
reading during reanalysis (Frazier & Rayner, 1982; Meseguer et al., 2002), though less
systematically than had initially been believed (Mitchell et al., 2008; von der Malsburg &
Vasishth, 2011, 2013). For local coherence sentences, Levy et al. (2009) found that readers
made more regressive eye movements and spent more time rereading earlier parts of the sen-
tence in (1un) compared to (1c) after having first fixated the verb tossed/thrown. Dans (1un), readers
were also more likely to refixate the preposition at than in (1c). This latter finding is consistent
with readers trying to resolve the conflict between the player having been attached as the
object of smiled at and the locally coherent attachment of the player as the subject of the

1 Note that we do not provide an exhaustive review of theories about local coherence effects that have been
proposed in the literature. Other accounts include those of Gibson (2006), Bicknell et al. (2009), Morgan et al.
(2010), and Hale (2011). See Paape and Vasishth (2016) for discussion.

OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science

43

je

D
o
w
n
o
un
d
e
d

F
r
o
m
h

t
t

p

:
/
/

d
je
r
e
c
t
.

m

je
t
.

/

e
d
toi
o
p
m

je
/

je

un
r
t
je
c
e

p
d

F
/

d
o

je
/

je

/

.

/

1
0
1
1
6
2
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
1
9
2
8
2
5
7
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
p
d

.

/

je

F

b
oui
g
toi
e
s
t

t

o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3

Local Coherence and Ungrammaticality

Paape, Vasishth, Engbert

would-be active verb tossed. Surtout, Levy et al. (2009) did not observe the same effect
when the preposition at was replaced with toward. They argue that the asymmetry is due to
toward being less easily confused with as or and, thus supporting the Levy (2008b) account
over the self-organized parsing account of Tabor et al. (2004).

In another set of two eye-tracking studies, Christianson et al. (2017) investigated targeted
regressions in locally coherent structures and classic garden-path structures. In one of their
experiments, they observed additional rereading of the region containing the preposition for
local coherence sentences. Cependant, regressions to precritical regions also occurred in con-
trol sentences similar to (1b), so it is not clear whether they were triggered by local coherence
per se. Christianson et al. (2017) conclude that participants in their study largely used reread-
ing to confirm their interpretation of the previous input, as opposed to revising their analysis.
En outre, given that comprehension accuracy was low even when rereading had occurred,
Christianson et al. (2017) suggest that participants engaged in superficial or “good enough”
traitement (par exemple., Christianson et al., 2001; Ferreira et al., 2002), possibly adopting syntactic
representations of the input. They speculate that “rereading may signal … a cobbling together
of several smaller interpretations based on substrings that are not fully integrated into a single
global structure” (p. 23). The notion of a “cobbled-together” analysis is compatible with a
self-organization mechanism, where partial parses compete with each other. Depending on
the implementation, the system may settle in a state in which either two globally incompatible
attachments are active at the same time, or in a state in which there is no chain of attachments
that spans the entire input (Forgeron, 2018). Cependant, given that Christianson et al.’s (2017)
interpretation of the reading patterns is speculative and based solely on the low comprehension
accuracy observed in their study, it is not clear which kinds of representations subjects ended up
avec, or how they were derived.

En résumé, evidence from eye-tracking studies does not decisively favor either the self-
organization or the uncertainty-based view of local coherence effects. This is especially true
given that regressions occur relatively rarely in the eye-tracking record, constituting only 10–
15% of all saccades (Rayner, 2009), and therefore relatively many observations are needed to
draw reliable conclusions about targeted regressions in particular. One aim of the current
study is to investigate whether the pattern of targeted regressions discovered by Levy et al.
(2009) can be replicated with a different kind of local coherence in a different language,
namely, German. We deviate from previous studies in that each sentence is followed by a
binary grammaticality judgment as opposed to a comprehension question. En théorie, such a
task may lead to more regressions compared to asking comprehension questions, as formal
features of the sentence become more important than meaning-related ones. We also test a
prediction derived from self-organized parsing, namely, that local coherence may result in
illusions of grammaticality: If a given sentence is globally ungrammatical but strongly locally
coherent, the local parse may act as the syntactic and semantic representation of the entire
input, leading to incorrect positive grammaticality judgments. Forgeron (2018) reports simulation
results from a self-organized parsing system that support this prediction: Given a specific set of
modeling assumptions, the system settled on the local parse in 18 out of 100 trials for the
English materials of Tabor et al. (2004).

Our study uses sentences such as (2).

(2) Man erfuhr

später, dass …

je

D
o
w
n
o
un
d
e
d

F
r
o
m
h

t
t

p

:
/
/

d
je
r
e
c
t
.

m

je
t
.

/

e
d
toi
o
p
m

je
/

je

un
r
t
je
c
e

p
d

F
/

d
o

je
/

je

.

/

/

1
0
1
1
6
2
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
1
9
2
8
2
5
7
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
p
d

/

.

je

F

b
oui
g
toi
e
s
t

t

o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3

One learned later
… einer der

Spitzel

que

un

of.the snitches

enttarnte Informanten warnten.
exposed informants warned.pl

OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science

44

Local Coherence and Ungrammaticality

Paape, Vasishth, Engbert

Verb-final word order is mandatory in German embedded clauses headed by the comple-
mentizer dass, “that,” unless the verb takes a sentential object. The embedded clause contains
an adjectival participle form such as enttarnte, “exposed,” that is superficially identical to the
third-person singular active form of the same verb. This results in a locally coherent subject-
verb-object (SVO) structure in which the syntactic object enttarnte Informanten, “exposed in-
formants,” could instead be analyzed as a verb-object sequence (see also Konieczny et al.,
2009; Paape & Vasishth, 2016). The sentence in (2) is globally ungrammatical, as the number
feature the subject noun phrase einer der Spitzel, “one of the snitches,” does not match the
number feature of the verb warnten, “warned.pl.” When subjects read the sentence and judge
its grammaticality, they may experience processing difficulty because there are two competing
syntactic analyses of the input that are somewhat attractive but are nevertheless both incorrect.
The two competing analyses are shown in (3) below. Note that when enttarnte, “exposed,” is
analyzed as a verb, the final verb warnten, “warned.pl,” is left without an attachment site.

(3)

je

D
o
w
n
o
un
d
e
d

F
r
o
m
h

t
t

p

:
/
/

d
je
r
e
c
t
.

m

je
t
.

/

e
d
toi
o
p
m

je
/

je

un
r
t
je
c
e

p
d

F
/

d
o

je
/

We now turn to our experimental study.

MATERIALS AND METHODS

Participants

je

/

.

/

1
0
1
1
6
2
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
1
9
2
8
2
5
7
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
p
d

.

/

je

Seventy-seven German native speakers were recruited from the local student population at the
University of Potsdam.2 All had normal or corrected-to-normal eyesight. They were paid 15A
as compensation for their participation.

Design and Stimuli

We preregistered our design and analysis, without theory-specific predictions, at https://osf.io
/ersxn. Our experiment followed a 2 × 2 design adapted from Paape and Vasishth (2016). Nous
manipulated the factors’ grammaticality (grammatical versus ungrammatical) and local coher-
ence (locally coherent versus not locally coherent). Grammaticality was manipulated by hav-
ing the final verb of the embedded clause correctly agree with the subject in number or not.
The would-be SOV structure is only locally coherent when the would-be active verb enttarnte,
“exposed,” agrees in number with the subject, and therefore local coherence can be manip-
ulated via the subject’s number feature. Thirty-two experimental items were created according

F

b
oui
g
toi
e
s
t

t

o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3

2 We had planned to test 80 participants, but remained three participants short of our goal due to project
constraints and participant recruitment issues.

OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science

45

Local Coherence and Ungrammaticality

Paape, Vasishth, Engbert

to the scheme shown in (4). Diamonds indicate region-of-interest boundaries in the example
stimulus.

(4) Preamble

später, } dass }
que

Man erfuhr
One learned later
Grammatical, Locally coherent
… einer der

Spitzel } enttarnte Informanten } [] } warnte.

un

of.the snitches exposed informants

warned.sg

Grammatical, Not locally coherent
… einige der

some of.the snitches exposed informants

Spitzel } enttarnte Informanten } [] } warnten.
warned.pl

Ungrammatical, Locally coherent
… einer der

Spitzel } enttarnte Informanten } [] } warnten.
warned.pl

of.the snitches exposed informants

un

Ungrammatical, Not locally coherent
… einige der

Spitzel } enttarnte Informanten } [] } warnte.

some of.the snitches exposed informants

warned.sg

The elided [] in the example was occupied by a prepositional phrase, in this case mit
raffinierten Tricks, “with subtle ploys.” The prepositional phrase was always three words long
and semantically compatible with both the global and the locally coherent analyses (“expose
with subtle ploys”/“warn with subtle ploys”).

Procedure

After giving informed consent, participants read the stimulus sentences and indicated after each
trial whether the sentence had been grammatical or not. The experimental sentences were pre-
sented according to a Latin-square design. They were mixed with 96 filler sentences containing
different kinds of grammatical violations, including agreement violations, case-marking errors,
as well as missing or added words. Dans l'ensemble, half of the sentences in the experiment were ungram-
matical. Presentation order was randomized at runtime. Participants were seated at a distance of
60 cm from the presentation screen, which had a resolution of 1920 × 1080 pixels. Sentences
were presented in 16 pt black Courier font on white background. Eye movements from the right
eye were recorded with an EyeLink 1000 Tower Mount eye-tracking system at a sampling
frequency of 1,000 Hz. Recalibration using a 9-point grid was carried out every 15 trials or as
needed. Drift correction was performed every six trials. Each trial started with the presentation of
a fixation cross at the position of the initial letter of the sentence. After participants fixated the
cross, the sentence was presented. Participants indicated that they wanted to continue to the
grammaticality judgment by looking in the lower right corner of the screen, then gave their judg-
ment by pressing one of two buttons on a VPixx RESPONSEPixx response box. The experiment
started with six practice sentences to familiarize participants with the procedure.

Data Analysis

Due to technical failures, no eye tracking data were collected for two participants. No accuracy
data were collected for six participants due to a programming error. Data from one additional
participant were removed because the participant failed to reach 50% accuracy on grammati-
cality judgments for the experimental items. All analyses of eye-tracking measures are thus based

OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science

46

je

D
o
w
n
o
un
d
e
d

F
r
o
m
h

t
t

p

:
/
/

d
je
r
e
c
t
.

m

je
t
.

/

e
d
toi
o
p
m

je
/

je

un
r
t
je
c
e

p
d

F
/

d
o

je
/

je

.

/

/

1
0
1
1
6
2
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
1
9
2
8
2
5
7
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
p
d

.

/

je

F

b
oui
g
toi
e
s
t

t

o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3

Local Coherence and Ungrammaticality

Paape, Vasishth, Engbert

on the data from 74 participants, while analyses of question responses are based on data from 68
participants.3 Fixations and saccades were computed from the raw data using the algorithm of
Engbert and Mergenthaler (2006). Fixations shorter than 20 ms were discarded and reading time
measures for the subject, objet, post-object, and verb regions were computed using the em2
package (Logac(cid:1)ev & Vasishth, 2013) in R (R Core Team, 2019). In an additional step that we had
not preregistered, for each reading time measure, data points below 80 ms were also discarded,
comme 80 ms have been estimated as the minimum amount of time within which linguistic informa-
tion can influence oculomotor control (Altmann, 2011). Statistical analyses were performed by
fitting fully hierarchical linear mixed models using the brms package (Bürkner, 2017). We ana-
lyzed log-transformed first-pass reading times, regression-path durations and total reading times,
in addition to log-transformed judgment response times.4 The analysis of judgment response
times included an additional shift parameter to account for motor execution time (Rouder,
2005). Fully hierarchical logistic regression models were used to analyze response accuracy
and regression probabilities. Both experimental factors were sum-coded, with grammatical
and locally coherent coded as 1 and ungrammatical and not locally coherent coded as −1.
Normal(0, 10) priors were used for intercepts and Normal(0, 1) priors5 were used for the slopes
across all analyses. LKJ priors (Lewandowski et al., 2009) were used for the correlation matrices,
with the ν parameter set to 2, making correlations near ±1 a priori less likely. Four sampling
chains with 2,000 iterations each were run for each model. The first 1,000 samples were dis-
carded as warmup. We treat effects as reliable if 95% of the posterior probability are either above
or below zero. Code and full posterior plots for all analyses, along with our experimental data
and analysis code are available at https://osf.io/f6ntk.

PREDICTIONS

Previous findings by Levy et al. (2009), Christianson et al. (2017), and Müller and Konieczny
(2019) indicate that processing disruption caused by local coherence should become visible in
first-pass reading times and regression-path durations. In our materials, the local coherence
begins at the object region, so that the disruption is predicted to occur in this region, either
because an error signal is triggered (Levy, 2008b) or because the locally coherent analysis
competes with the global one (Tabor et al., 2004).

je

D
o
w
n
o
un
d
e
d

F
r
o
m
h

t
t

p

:
/
/

d
je
r
e
c
t
.

m

je
t
.

/

e
d
toi
o
p
m

je
/

je

un
r
t
je
c
e

p
d

F
/

d
o

je
/

je

.

/

/

1
0
1
1
6
2
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
1
9
2
8
2
5
7
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
p
d

.

/

je

F

b
oui
g
toi
e
s
t

t

o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3

Self-Organized Parsing Models

There exists, to our knowledge, no implemented model that spells out the assumed connec-
tions between a self-organized parser and the eye movement control system. Accordingly, any
experimental outcome in which the eye movement record shows an indication of processing
difficulty—longer reading times and/or regressions—in the conditions where self-organized
parsing predicts increased competition is, in principle, compatible with the theory.

3 As stated in the preregistration, all participants completed an operation-span test as a measure of working
memory capacity prior to the experiment. These data were collected mainly for use in later stages of the project,
where we intend to build a computational model that accounts for a variety of sentence-processing phenomena.
We had no specific predictions regarding interactions between memory capacity and local coherence, and en-
tering the memory measure into our current analyses yielded no informative interactions with the experimental
manipulations, so that we refrain from reporting the results here.
4 First-pass reading time is the sum of all fixation durations from first entering a region from the left prior to
leaving it in any direction. Regression-path duration, also called go-past time, is first-pass reading time plus the
sum of all fixations on earlier regions before passing the region to the right. Total reading time is the sum of all
fixations in a region over the entire trial.
5 We deviated from the preregistered Normal(0, 5) priors here because sampling is faster for more narrow
priors and effects are not realistically expected to be larger than 2 log ms.

OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science

47

Local Coherence and Ungrammaticality

Paape, Vasishth, Engbert

The predictions of the self-organized model depend on when the system settles on an analysis. If
the system does not settle before the entire input has been processed, readers may experience pro-
longed processing difficulty until the final region, due to competition between the local and global
analyses. Alternativement, if the competition is short-lived and the system settles on an analysis already
at the object region, no prolonged difficulty is expected. Predictions for the sentence-final region also
depend on whether the system has settled on an analysis: If the parser has settled on the locally co-
herent parse, ungrammaticality of the global analysis presumably should not matter, and processing
difficulty should thus not differ between grammatical and ungrammatical sentences. This prediction
assumes that the parser can settle on sufficiently well-formed (“harmonious”) structures even if not all
words in the sentence have been integrated into the structure, as in the implementation of Smith
(2018). Cependant, given that the local analysis does not constitute a grammatical analysis of the entire
input string, processing difficulty should nevertheless be higher than in grammatical sentences. Par
contraste, if the system has not settled on an analysis, competition should be greater between the local
and global analyses when the global analysis is ungrammatical, because the two analyses will be
closer to each other in well-formedness. In grammatical sentences, on the other hand, the globally
correct analysis should outcompete the local one more quickly. Under both scenarios, a statistical
interaction between local coherence and grammaticality is predicted in the final region.

Regarding the off-line judgments, if readers sometimes settle on the locally coherent analysis in
ungrammatical sentences, they may experience illusions of grammaticality, leading to ungram-
matical, locally coherent sentences being incorrectly judged as grammatical. Nevertheless, due
to the lower harmony of the local coherence structure, there should be fewer positive grammat-
icality judgments than for grammatical sentences. Par contre, if readers are merely temporarily
confused by the local coherence but do not adopt the incorrect parse, there should be no illusions
of grammaticality. Konieczny (2005) found that participants took longer to notice ungrammatical-
ity in locally coherent versus not locally coherent sentences, so we expect to find the same pattern
in our study. Depending on when readers finish evaluating the sentence’s grammaticality, le
effect may either appear in the final region of the sentence or in judgment response times.

Noisy-Channel Model

Unlike self-organized parsing models, the noisy-channel model has no way of settling on ungram-
matical structures, but is bound by grammatical self-consistency. Ainsi, the only scenario in which
illusions of grammaticality could arise for ungrammatical, locally coherent sentences is one in
which participants come to doubt the previous input and then fail to verify their revised belief about
previous words’ identity through rereading. Essentially, in such trials the participant would come to
believe that they are reading a main clause, and ignore the evidence to the contrary. Surtout,
illusions of grammaticality should only arise if readers also ignore the sentence-final verb, because
its presence is a strong indication that a main clause analysis is not tenable, even in ungrammatical
phrases. Given that the noisy-channel model as formulated by Levy (2008b) only accounts for
changes to previous but not to future input, it is thus unlikely that illusions of grammaticality should
occur at all.

In the noisy-channel model, an error signal is raised when readers experience changes in their
belief about previous input. The larger the change in belief, the larger the error signal. Cependant,
the strength of the error signal also depends on how easily the veridical input string can be edited
into a “near-neighbor” string, such as at to as. The more distant the two strings are, the smaller the
change in belief, given that smaller corruptions of the input in the noisy channel are more likely
than larger corruptions. The model allows for deletions, insertions and substitutions of characters,
and the penalty to the belief change incurred is proportional to the Levensthein distance between

OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science

48

je

D
o
w
n
o
un
d
e
d

F
r
o
m
h

t
t

p

:
/
/

d
je
r
e
c
t
.

m

je
t
.

/

e
d
toi
o
p
m

je
/

je

un
r
t
je
c
e

p
d

F
/

d
o

je
/

je

.

/

/

1
0
1
1
6
2
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
1
9
2
8
2
5
7
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
p
d

.

/

je

F

b
oui
g
toi
e
s
t

t

o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3

Local Coherence and Ungrammaticality

Paape, Vasishth, Engbert

the veridical string and the transformed string.6 For our materials, there is only one set of transfor-
mations that we can think of that would license the local parse: Editing out the complementizer,
adding a colon7 and capitalizing the first letter of the subject noun phrase, which turns the sub-
ordinate clause into a main clause with SVO word order, as shown in (5).

The edit distance here is twice as large as that assumed for the largest edits in the English
materials, such as inserting who between player and tossed.8 The strength of the error signal
also depends on whether enttarnte, “exposed,” is much more likely to appear as a finite verb
in the edited main clause than as an adjective in the unedited subordinate clause. According
to our seach in the TIGER treebank (Brants et al., 2002), the conditional probability of encoun-
tering a determiner-less, adjective-modified object noun phrase after a complementizer and a
subject noun phrase (NP) is about 1.2%. By comparison, the conditional probability of en-
countering a finite verb directly after a colon and a subject NP is about 25%. In English, en utilisant
the numbers obtained by Levy (2008b), the conditional probability of encountering a reduced
relative clause after an NP is about 1.5%, compared to a 91% probability of encountering a
finite verb after a subject NP. The local parse given the necessary edits is thus about 60 times
more likely in the English materials and about 21 times more likely in the German materials.
Based on the increased edit distance and the smaller change in conditional probability, le
error signal should thus be much weaker in the German materials.

The hallmark prediction of the noisy-channel approach that was tested by Levy et al. (2009)
is that readers make targeted regressions to previous words whose identity they have come to
doubt. For the investigation of targeted regressions, the em2 package allows the computation
of so-called conditional rereading measures, c'est, measures that are contingent on a certain
region in the sentence having been fixated prior to the rereading of an earlier region. Fixations
on the “target” region are registered until the “source” region is passed to the right. We com-
pute conditional rereading probabilities for three theoretically interesting target and source re-
gions in the sentence and make predictions as shown in Table 1.

6 Assuming that all edit operations are equally likely, it is irrelevant for the edit distance measure whether the
veridical or the nonveridical sentence is taken as the “source” representation: From the reader’s point of view,
the perceived sentence may appear like a corruption of an original, intended sentence—this is the idea behind
the noisy-channel model—but from the experimenter’s perspective, the reader’s inferred representation is a cor-
ruption of the actual presented sentence. For reasons of expository ease, we present the experimenter’s
perspective.
7 See Levy (2011) for another application of the noisy-channel model that includes punctuation.
8 Note that the comparison rests on the assumption by Levy (2008b) that edits are character-based. If edits are
instead assumed to be word-based (Gibson et al., 2013), the contrast between our materials and the English
examples is somewhat less stark.

OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science

49

je

D
o
w
n
o
un
d
e
d

F
r
o
m
h

t
t

p

:
/
/

d
je
r
e
c
t
.

m

je
t
.

/

e
d
toi
o
p
m

je
/

je

un
r
t
je
c
e

p
d

F
/

d
o

je
/

je

.

/

/

1
0
1
1
6
2
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
1
9
2
8
2
5
7
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
p
d

.

/

je

F

b
oui
g
toi
e
s
t

t

o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3

Local Coherence and Ungrammaticality

Paape, Vasishth, Engbert

Tableau 1.

Predictions for conditional rereading probabilities derived from the noisy-channel

model. > indicates higher probability.

Source

Object

Target
Complementizer

exposed informants

que

End of sentence

Object

je

II

warned

exposed informants

III

End of sentence

Subject

warned

One/some of the snitches

Prediction

Locally coherent >

Not locally coherent

Locally coherent >

Not locally coherent

Ungrammatical >
Grammatical

Prediction I arises straightforwardly under the noisy-channel view, because reading the locally
coherent object region may cause readers to check whether they are, in fact, reading a subordinate
clause headed by dass, “that,” in which case the locally coherent parse is disallowed, in analogy to
rereading the problematic word at in the English stimuli. Prediction II arises because encountering
a verb at the end of the sentence is again clear evidence that the locally coherent region cannot
also contain a verb, which may trigger confirmatory rereading. This prediction presupposes that
the error signal triggered by the locally coherent adjective does not always immediately lead to
regressions, but that readers may wait until further input is processed. Prediction III arises because
encountering a verb with incorrect number marking could trigger uncertainty as to what the num-
ber feature of the subject phrase was, triggering confirmatory rereading.

RÉSULTATS

Tableau 2 shows grammaticality judgment accuracy and mean response times by condition.
Chiffre 1 shows reading measures by condition and region of interest.

Judgment Response Times and Accuracy

There was no indication that the experimental manipulations affected judgment response
times, but response accuracy was lower for ungrammatical compared to grammatical sen-

tences (

^Δ = −4%, CrI [credible interval]: [−7%, 0%]).

Subject Region (one/some of the snitches)

Total reading times in the subject region were longer in ungrammatical compared to grammat-

ical sentences (

^Δ = 105 ms, CrI: [51 ms, 160 ms]).9

9 There was also some indication that first-pass reading times were increased in locally coherent sentences in the
^Δ = 28 ms, CrI: [−6 ms,
subject region, with the effect being just slightly below our predefined reliability criterion (
61 ms]). The difference may indicate a parafoveal preview effect, but a word-by-word analysis using successive
differences contrasts reveals that conditions diverge at einer/einige, “one/some,” after which the difference disap-
pears and only reappears at the would-be verb of the local coherence (see Supplementary Materials at https://osf.io
/f6ntk). We speculate that the effect may be due to einer, “one,” being semantically more specific than einige,
“some.”

OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science

50

je

D
o
w
n
o
un
d
e
d

F
r
o
m
h

t
t

p

:
/
/

d
je
r
e
c
t
.

m

je
t
.

/

e
d
toi
o
p
m

je
/

je

un
r
t
je
c
e

p
d

F
/

d
o

je
/

je

.

/

/

1
0
1
1
6
2
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
1
9
2
8
2
5
7
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
p
d

/

.

je

F

b
oui
g
toi
e
s
t

t

o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3

Local Coherence and Ungrammaticality

Paape, Vasishth, Engbert

Tableau 2. Grammaticality judgment accuracy and mean response times by condition.

Grammaticality
Grammatical

Local coherence
Not locally coherent

p(correct)
91% [87%, 94%]

(cid:3)RT (ms)
662 [576, 749]

Grammatical

Locally coherent

90% [86%, 94%]

654 [576, 733]

Ungrammatical

Not locally coherent

84% [80%, 89%]

616 [551, 681]

Ungrammatical

Locally coherent

87% [83%, 91%]

677 [576, 778]

Object Region (exposed informants)

First-pass reading times in the object region were increased in locally coherent compared to
^Δ = 73 ms, CrI: [34 ms, 111 ms]). Regression-path durations in
not locally coherent sentences (
the object region were also longer in locally coherent compared to not locally coherent sen-

tences (

^Δ = 38 ms, CrI: [−3 ms, 80 ms]).

Post-Object Region ( with subtle ploys)

^Δ =
There was an interaction between grammaticality and local coherence at the post-object region (
−33 ms, CrI: [−66 ms, 0 ms]), mainly due to longer regression-path durations in locally coherent,
^Δ = 41 ms, CrI: [−4 ms, 88 ms]). As the grammaticality of a given sentence
grammatical sentences (
is only determined in the sentence-final region, we assume that the pattern is either spurious or
due to parafoveal preview. Total reading times for the post-object region where shorter in ungram-

matical than in grammatical sentences (

^Δ = −77 ms, CrI: [−135 ms, −20 ms]).

Final Region ( warned)

grammatical sentences (

grammatical sentences (

grammaticality and local coherence (

In the sentence-final region, first-pass reading times were longer in ungrammatical compared to
^Δ = 35 ms, CrI: [9 ms, 62 ms]). There was also an interaction between
^Δ = 34 ms, CrI: [1 ms, 69 ms]), mainly due to shorter first-pass
^Δ = −45 ms, CrI: [−84 ms, −7 ms]). Là
reading times in locally coherent, grammatical sentences (
were more first-pass regressions from the sentence-final region in ungrammatical compared to
^Δ = 0.07, CrI: [0.02, 0.12]). Regression-path durations in the sentence-final
^Δ = 113 ms, CrI: [−14 ms, 238 ms]),
^Δ = −115 ms,
mainly due to shorter regression paths in locally coherent, grammatical sentences (
CrI: [−268 ms, 37 ms]). Total reading times in this region were longer for ungrammatical compared
^Δ =
to grammatical sentences (
88 ms, CrI: [48 ms, 129 ms]), due to local coherence leading to shorter total reading times in
^Δ = −103 ms, CrI: [−151 ms, −55 ms]), but longer total reading times in

^Δ = 69 ms, CrI: [30 ms, 108 ms]). Encore, there was an interaction (

region showed the same interaction as first-pass reading times (

grammatical sentences (

ungrammatical sentences (

^Δ = 69 ms, CrI: [30 ms, 107 ms]).

Conditional Refixations

clude the subject region (

In ungrammatical sentences, regression paths starting at the final verb were more likely to in-
^Δ = 15%, CrI: [9%, 21%]) but less likely to include the sentence
^Δ = −5%, CrI: [−9%, 0%]) compared to grammatical sentences. There was no

preamble (

OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science

51

je

D
o
w
n
o
un
d
e
d

F
r
o
m
h

t
t

p

:
/
/

d
je
r
e
c
t
.

m

je
t
.

/

e
d
toi
o
p
m

je
/

je

un
r
t
je
c
e

p
d

F
/

d
o

je
/

je

.

/

/

1
0
1
1
6
2
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
1
9
2
8
2
5
7
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
p
d

.

/

je

F

b
oui
g
toi
e
s
t

t

o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3

Local Coherence and Ungrammaticality

Paape, Vasishth, Engbert

je

D
o
w
n
o
un
d
e
d

F
r
o
m
h

t
t

p

:
/
/

d
je
r
e
c
t
.

m

je
t
.

/

e
d
toi
o
p
m

je
/

je

un
r
t
je
c
e

p
d

F
/

d
o

je
/

je

.

/

/

1
0
1
1
6
2
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
1
9
2
8
2
5
7
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
p
d

/

.

je

F

b
oui
g
toi
e
s
t

t

o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3

Chiffre 1. Reading measures by region of interest and condition. Error bars show 95% confidence intervals based on participant means.

indication of the other refixation patterns predicted by the noisy-channel approach.10
Cependant, we also conducted an exploratory analysis of all regression paths starting at or after
the object region, coding trials with at least one regression from any postsubject region versus
trials with no regressions. In this analysis, there was some weak indication that the

10 Our preregistration also contained a prediction for additional targeted regressions from the object region to
the subject region in locally coherent sentences, due to participants checking agreement between the subject
and the would-be verb. This prediction was not borne out either.

OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science

52

Local Coherence and Ungrammaticality

Paape, Vasishth, Engbert

Chiffre 2. Gauche: Refixations on the complementizer dass, “that,” after reading the locally coherent
region, by condition. Middle: Refixations on the subject region after reading the sentence-final
verb, by condition. Droite: Refixations on the preamble region after reading the sentence-final
verb, by condition. Error bars show 95% confidence intervals based on participant means. Note
the different scales.

complementizer dass, “that,” was fixated more often in the locally coherent conditions (
3%, CrI: [−1%, 7%]). The data underlying these analyses are shown in Figure 2.

^Δ =

DISCUSSION

Local coherence led to increased first-pass reading times and regression-path durations in the
object region (enttarnte Informanten, “exposed informants”), where the local parse became
available, in line with findings by Bicknell et al. (2009), Levy et al. (2009), Christianson
et autres. (2017), et, more recently, by Müller and Konieczny (2019). There was some weak in-
dication of local coherence triggering targeted regressions, as predicted by the noisy-channel
model: While there was no indication that the local coherence immediately triggered regres-
sions to the complementizer dass, “that,” regression paths starting at any point from the object
phrase onward were more likely to include the complementizer by about 3% (CrI: [−1%, 7%])
in the locally coherent conditions. The effect is small and its credible interval includes zero,
despite our sample being almost twice as large as that of Levy et al. (2009) and the paradigm
being relatively efficient at triggering regressions: Dans l'ensemble, at least one interregion regression
was made on 79% of trials for experimental sentences (CrI: [73%, 85%]), and the mean num-
ber of refixated regions per trial for these items was 2.3 (CrI: [2, 2.6]). Our paradigm was also,
in principle, able to trigger targeted rereading. This is supported by the observation of more
refixations of the subject region (15%, CrI: [9%, 21%]) and fewer refixations of the sentence
preamble (−5%, CrI: [−9%, 0%]) in ungrammatical sentences. Participants presumably tar-
geted the subject region to check whether the sentence was indeed ungrammatical. The find-
ing is in line with the noisy-channel model, but could also be captured by other models,
assuming that there is a strong link between attention and gaze location.

There is a question of whether a 3% increase in refixations of the complementizer provides
convincing support for the noisy-channel model. Bayes factors can be used to quantify the
evidence in favor of such an effect over the evidence in favor of the null hypothesis, which is
that there is no effect of local coherence on refixations of the complementizer. We computed
Bayes factors using bridge sampling (Meng & Wong, 1996). Given that vague priors lead to bias
in favor of the null model (Lee & Wagenmakers, 2014), we also computed Bayes factors for
two narrower priors, as shown in Table 3.

Assuming that previous results by Levy et al. (2009), who observed an increase of about 4% dans
refixations of the critical preposition, generalize to our German construction, assuming a small
effect with a positive sign seems reasonable. On the other hand, if one does not subscribe to

OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science

53

je

D
o
w
n
o
un
d
e
d

F
r
o
m
h

t
t

p

:
/
/

d
je
r
e
c
t
.

m

je
t
.

/

e
d
toi
o
p
m

je
/

je

un
r
t
je
c
e

p
d

F
/

d
o

je
/

je

/

/

.

1
0
1
1
6
2
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
1
9
2
8
2
5
7
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
p
d

/

.

je

F

b
oui
g
toi
e
s
t

t

o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3

Local Coherence and Ungrammaticality

Paape, Vasishth, Engbert

Bayes factors (BF) for the effect of local coherence on refixations of the complementizer

Tableau 3.
under different priors. A half-normal distribution is a normal distribution that is left-truncated at
zero, thus restricting the prior to positive values. BF values >1 indicate evidence in favor of the null
hypothèse.

Prior
Normal(0, 1)

Normal(0, 0.1)

Half-Normal(0.1)

Prior 95% CrI
[−62%, 62%]

[−7%, 7%]

[0%, 8%]

BF01
7.14

1.05

0.49

the noisy-channel model, other accounts of local coherence effects may predict fixations to be
drawn away from the complementizer to other regions of the sentence, such as the beginning
of the sentence or the locally coherent region, suggesting a wider prior. As expected, the null hy-
pothesis is strongly favored under a wide prior, with the evidence tipping in favor of the alternative
hypothesis under the narrowest prior. Nevertheless, the evidence in favor of the alternative hy-
pothesis is still “weak” or “anecdotal” under this prior (Jeffreys, 1939/1998; Raftery, 1995). Notre
findings are thus compatible with the predictions of the noisy-channel model under a broad con-
strual, but cannot be taken to directly support it, given that the analysis was exploratory in nature.
Further confirmatory research is clearly needed.

Our findings are also compatible with the notion that rereading is largely confirmatory in
local coherence structures (Christianson et al., 2017; Levy et al., 2009). Par exemple, there is
no indication in our data that local coherence resulted in a complete revision of readers’ be-
liefs about the previous input: If readers had sometimes come to believe that they were reading
a main clause, the sentence-final verb should have been highly surprising on such trials.
Contrary to this possible prediction, there was no main effect of local coherence in any mea-
sure for the final region of the sentence; in fact, the numerical tendency for each of the three
reading-time measures points in the opposite direction. This is broadly consistent with a ver-
sion of the model in which readers always act on and eventually overcome uncertainty by
“checking” previous input (overtly or covertly) when given the opportunity.11

There is no indication in our data that the availability of a locally coherent subparse leads to
illusions of grammaticality in otherwise ungrammatical sentences. The prediction of self-
organized processing models that the local analysis may outcompete the global one in ungram-
matical sentences was thus not borne out in our stimuli. The null result is also in line with the
findings of Konieczny (2005), who also found no indication of local coherence affecting the ac-
curacy of grammatical error detection in German, albeit using a different type of structure. While
we found no effects of the experimental manipulations on judgment response times, the pattern
seen in total reading times in the sentence-final region is compatible with Konieczny’s (2005) find-
ing that ungrammatical sentences take longer to reject in the presence of local coherence.

Do Grammaticality and Local Coherence Interact? Investigating a Confound

The only robust interaction between the local coherence and grammaticality manipulations
appeared across measures in the final region of the sentence, where agreement of the lexical
verb with the sentential subject was either correct or not. The effect of local coherence in

11 Note, cependant, that this interpretation may be at odds with the findings of Gibson et al. (2013), où
participants had ample opportunity to reread sentences and still gave interpretations that were inconsistent with
the literal input. Par contre, it is not at odds with the findings of Levy (2011), where downstream effects of
possible local edits were observed, as the self-paced reading paradigm did not allow readers to overtly regress.

OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science

54

je

D
o
w
n
o
un
d
e
d

F
r
o
m
h

t
t

p

:
/
/

d
je
r
e
c
t
.

m

je
t
.

/

e
d
toi
o
p
m

je
/

je

un
r
t
je
c
e

p
d

F
/

d
o

je
/

je

/

/

.

1
0
1
1
6
2
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
1
9
2
8
2
5
7
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
p
d

.

/

je

F

b
oui
g
toi
e
s
t

t

o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3

Local Coherence and Ungrammaticality

Paape, Vasishth, Engbert

ungrammatical sentences is compatible with competition between the ungrammatical global
analysis and the locally coherent analysis, as predicted by self-organized sentence processing.
On the other hand, the speedup due to local coherence in grammatical sentences is unexpected.
Readers may have suppressed the locally coherent parse during first-pass reading of the object
region, forming a strong prediction about the upcoming verb’s number feature. In grammatical
phrases, the prediction is borne out because verb carries the expected number feature, et
processing is faster the locally coherent condition. In ungrammatical sentences, the prediction
is not borne out and processing is slower in the locally coherent condition due to increased
surprisal (Hale, 2001; Levy, 2008un).

Cependant, this speculative explanation is called into question by the fact that our study con-
founded grammaticality and local coherence with the number feature of the sentence-final
verb: The two slowest conditions in total reading times had plural verbs while the two faster
conditions had singular verbs. Recoding the experimental factors accordingly, the grammati-
cality × local coherence interaction turns into a main effect of verb plurality (see following).12
Plural verbs may be more difficult to process than singular verbs because they are orthograph-
ically longer and morphologically more complex, or because plural number is more marked
than singular number (par exemple., Eberhard, 1997). In order to investigate this possibility, we con-
ducted a web-based self-paced reading experiment with 69 participants that used the same
materials (including the same fillers) and the same task as our eye-tracking study, but removed
all locally coherent adjectives and replaced them with either definite articles, quantifiers, ou
unambiguous adjectives.13 The reading time results for the sentence-final verb are compatible
with verb plurality being the source of the interaction: Reading times were slower for ungram-
^Δ = 174 ms, CrI: [122 ms, 226 ms]) and also for sentences with plural verbs
matical sentences (
^Δ = 51 ms, CrI: [10 ms, 91 ms]), resulting in a pattern that qualitatively matches that found in
(
the eye-tracking study, as shown in Figure 3.

These additional results cast heavy doubt on the interpretation of the reading patterns ob-
served in the main experiment as being due to an interaction between local coherence and
grammaticality. While such an interaction may underlyingly be present, it would need to be
tested more thoroughly in a design without the number confound.

Self-Organized Processing and Noisy-Channel Models—The Broader Picture

When interpreting the current findings in relation to the larger theoretical picture, one also needs
to keep in mind that the strength of local coherence effects may depend heavily on the type of
structure used. Garden-path effects are known to differ in magnitude depending on the kind of
ambiguity used (par exemple., Sturt et al., 1999), with differences between ambiguity types going beyond
what differences in predictability can account for (van Schijndel & Linzen, 2018). In this context,
recall that Tabor et al. (2004) found more rejections of sentences containing English reduced
relative clauses in the presence of local coherence, despite the fact that the sentences’ actual
grammaticality remained unchanged. It could thus be argued that the self-organized approach
would have predicted illusions of ungrammaticality rather than grammaticality for our sen-
tences. Neither illusion was observed in our data. Cependant, unlike our stimuli, which are per-
fectly natural for German readers, reduced relative clauses are known to be troublesome for
English readers (Bever, 1970) and have been argued to be of dubious grammaticality under some
conditions (McKoon & Ratcliff, 2003). Given these differences, a self-organized sentence

12 For further reading on how interactions can be recast as main effects, see Vasishth (2018) and Westfall
(2015).
13 Further information about the experiment can be found at https://osf.io/f6ntk.

OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science

55

je

D
o
w
n
o
un
d
e
d

F
r
o
m
h

t
t

p

:
/
/

d
je
r
e
c
t
.

m

je
t
.

/

e
d
toi
o
p
m

je
/

je

un
r
t
je
c
e

p
d

F
/

d
o

je
/

je

/

/

.

1
0
1
1
6
2
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
1
9
2
8
2
5
7
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
p
d

/

.

je

F

b
oui
g
toi
e
s
t

t

o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3

Local Coherence and Ungrammaticality

Paape, Vasishth, Engbert

Chiffre 3. Comparison of reading times at the sentence-final region between eye-tracking and self-
paced reading experiments. Error bars show 95% confidence intervals based on participant means.

processing model with the right parameter settings may be able to account for all the available
data from both English and German. As the self-organized approach to sentence processing is
still relatively young and implementation details differ between iterations, it remains to be seen
whether a consensus model will emerge anytime soon. One key challenge is to explain the data
of Levy et al. (2009), lequel, besides showing some evidence for targeted regressions, also sug-
gest a role of orthographic or phonological similarity to “neighboring” words, as in the case of at
versus as. The self-organized model of Kukona et al. (2014), which includes word recognition in
addition to parsing and has been used to model fixation patterns in visual world experiments,
could conceivably be extended to explain these patterns.

For the noisy-channel model of Levy (2008b), there are also considerable degrees of free-
dom with regard to the assumed link between error signal strength and eye movements, aussi
as possible effects of task manipulations on the model’s noise parameter, which influences the
edit penalties. As our experiment contained ungrammatical sentences, participants may have
inferred a higher level of noise in our stimuli compared to the studies of Tabor et al. (2004) et
Levy et al. (2009) (see also Gibson et al., 2013). Relatedly, a more recent version of the noisy-
channel account (Futrell et al., 2020) has been argued to account for illusions of grammaticality
in complex English sentences, so that evidence for such illusions in locally coherent sentences,
had we found any, would not have decisively favored the self-organized approach. Cependant, comme
the account of Futrell et al. (2020) rests on readers completely forgetting about earlier parts of the
sentence, it is unclear whether it can also plausibly account for illusions in short, simple sentences.
Dans l'ensemble, collecting more high-quality data from different languages, using different experimental
paradigms and different structures, and deriving testable predictions from implemented processing
models will help to further disentangle the different existing accounts of local coherence effects.

REMERCIEMENTS

The authors would like to thank Daniela Mertzen, Maximilian Rabe, and the audience at
AMLaP 2019 in Moscow for fruitful discussions. Further thanks go to Sarah Risse and Hans
Trukenbrod for assistance with the implementation of the experiment.

INFORMATIONS SUR LE FINANCEMENT

SV, Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (https://dx.doi.org/10.13039/501100001659), Award ID:
317633480. RE, Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (https://dx.doi.org/10.13039/501100001659),
Award ID: 317633480.

OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science

56

je

D
o
w
n
o
un
d
e
d

F
r
o
m
h

t
t

p

:
/
/

d
je
r
e
c
t
.

m

je
t
.

/

e
d
toi
o
p
m

je
/

je

un
r
t
je
c
e

p
d

F
/

d
o

je
/

je

/

.

/

1
0
1
1
6
2
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
1
9
2
8
2
5
7
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
p
d

/

.

je

F

b
oui
g
toi
e
s
t

t

o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3

Local Coherence and Ungrammaticality

Paape, Vasishth, Engbert

CONTRIBUTIONS DES AUTEURS

DP: Conceptualisation: Equal; Conservation des données: Lead; Analyse formelle: Lead; Enquête: Lead;
Méthodologie: Equal; Gestion de projet: Supporting; Logiciel: Supporting; Écriture – originale
brouillon: Lead; Rédaction – révision & édition: Equal. SV: Conceptualisation: Equal; Acquisition de financement:
Lead; Méthodologie: Equal; Gestion de projet: Lead; Ressources: Supporting; Logiciel:
Supporting; Surveillance: Lead; Rédaction – révision & édition: Equal. RE: Conceptualisation:
Supporting; Acquisition de financement: Lead; Méthodologie: Equal; Gestion de projet: Lead;
Ressources: Lead; Logiciel: Supporting; Surveillance: Lead; Rédaction – révision & édition: Equal.

RÉFÉRENCES

Altmann, G. T. (2011). Language can mediate eye movement control
within 100 millisecondes, regardless of whether there is anything
to move the eyes to. Acta Psychologica, 137(2), 190–200. https://
doi.org/10.1016/j.actpsy.2010.09.009, PubMed: 20965479

Bever, T. G. (1970). The cognitive basis for linguistic structure. In J. R..
Hayes (Ed.), Cognitive development of language (pp. 279–352).
Wiley.

Bicknell, K., Levy, R., & Demberg, V. (2009). Correcting the incor-
rect: Local coherence effects modeled with prior belief update.
Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics
Society, 35(1), 13–24. https://doi.org/10.3765/bls.v35i1.3594
Brants, S., Dipper, S., Hansen, S., Lezius, W., & Forgeron, G. (2002).
The TIGER treebank. Proceedings of the Workshop on Treebanks
and Linguistic Theories, 168, 24–41.

Bürkner, P.-C. (2017). brms: An R package for Bayesian multilevel
models using Stan. Journal of Statistical Software, 80(1), 1–28.
https://doi.org/10.18637/jss.v080.i01

Christianson, K., Hollingworth, UN., Halliwell, J.. F., & Ferreira, F.
(2001). Thematic roles assigned along the garden path linger.
Psychologie Cognitive, 42(4), 368–407. https://doi.org/10.1006
/cogp.2001.0752, PubMed: 11368528

Christianson, K., Luke, S. G., Hussey, E. K., & Wochna, K. L. (2017).
Why reread? Evidence from garden-path and local coherence
structures. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology,
70(7), 1380–1405. https://doi.org/10.1080/17470218.2016
.1186200, PubMed: 27150840

Eberhard, K. M.. (1997). The marked effect of number on subject–verb
agreement. Journal of Memory and Language, 36(2), 147–164.
https://doi.org/10.1006/jmla.1996.2484

Engbert, R., & Mergenthaler, K. (2006). Microsaccades are triggered
by low retinal image slip. Proceedings of the National Academy
of Sciences, 103(18), 7192–7197. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas
.0509557103, PubMed: 16632611

Ferreira, F., Bailey, K. G., & Ferraro, V. (2002). Good-enough rep-
resentations in language comprehension. Current Directions in
Sciences psychologiques, 11(1), 11–15. https://doi.org/10.1111
/1467-8721.00158

Frazier, L., & Rayner, K. (1982). Making and correcting errors during
sentence comprehension: Eye movements in the analysis of
structurally ambiguous sentences. Psychologie Cognitive, 14(2),
178–210. https://est ce que je.org/10.1016/0010-0285(82)90008-1

Futrell, R., Gibson, E., & Levy, R.. P.. (2020). Lossy-context surprisal:
An information-theoretic model of memory effects in sentence
traitement. Sciences cognitives, 44(3), Article e12814. https://est ce que je
.org/10.1111/cogs.12814, PubMed: 32100918

Gibson, E. (2006). The interaction of top–down and bottom–up sta-
tistics in the resolution of syntactic category ambiguity. Journal de

Memory and Language, 54(3), 363–388. https://est ce que je.org/10.1016/j
.jml.2005.12.005

Gibson, E., Bergen, L., & Piantadosi, S. T. (2013). Rational integration
of noisy evidence and prior semantic expectations in sentence
interpretation. Actes de l'Académie nationale des sciences,
110(20), 8051–8056. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1216438110,
PubMed: 23637344

Hale, J.. T. (2001). A probabilistic Earley parser as a psycholinguistic
model. Proceedings of the Second Meeting of the North American
Chapter of the Association for Computational Linguistics on
Language Technologies, 103(18), 7192–7197. https://est ce que je.org/10
.3115/1073336.1073357

Hale, J.. T. (2011). What a rational parser would do. Cognitive
Science, 35(3), 399–443. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1551-6709
.2010.01145.X

Jeffreys, H. (1998). The theory of probability. Oxford University

Presse. (Original work published 1939)

Konieczny, L. (2005). The psychological reality of local coherences
in sentence processing. In B. G. Bara, L. W. Barsalou, & M..
Bucciarelli (Éd.), Proceedings of the 27th Annual Conference
of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 1178–1183). Cognitive
Science Society.

Konieczny, L., Müller, D., Hachmann, W., Schwarzkopf, S., & Wolfer, S.
(2009). Local syntactic coherence interpretation: Evidence from
a visual world study. In N. UN. Taatgen & H. van Rijn (Éd.),
Proceedings of the 31st Annual Conference of the Cognitive
Science Society (pp. 1133–1138). Cognitive Science Society.
Kukona, UN., Cho, P.. W., Magnuson, J.. S., & Tabor, W. (2014).
Lexical interference effects in sentence processing: Evidence
from the visual world paradigm and self-organizing models.
Journal de psychologie expérimentale: Apprentissage, Mémoire, et
Cognition, 40(2), 326–347. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0034903,
PubMed: 24245535

Lee, M.. D., & Wagenmakers, E.-J. (2014). Bayesian cognitive

modeling: A practical course. la presse de l'Universite de Cambridge.

Levy, R.. (2008un). Expectation-based syntactic comprehension.
Cognition, 106(3), 1126–1177. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition
.2007.05.006, PubMed: 17662975

Levy, R.. (2008b). A noisy-channel model of human sentence
comprehension under uncertain input. En M. Lapata & H. T. Ng
(Éd.), Actes du 2008 Conference on Empirical Methods
in Natural Language Processing (pp. 234–243). Association for
Computational Linguistics. https://doi.org/10.3115/1613715
.1613749

Levy, R.. (2011). Integrating surprisal and uncertain-input models in
online sentence comprehension: Formal techniques and empiri-
cal results. In A. Way & P.. Pantel (Éd.), Proceedings of the 49th

OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science

57

je

D
o
w
n
o
un
d
e
d

F
r
o
m
h

t
t

p

:
/
/

d
je
r
e
c
t
.

m

je
t
.

/

e
d
toi
o
p
m

je
/

je

un
r
t
je
c
e

p
d

F
/

d
o

je
/

je

/

/

.

1
0
1
1
6
2
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
1
9
2
8
2
5
7
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
p
d

.

/

je

F

b
oui
g
toi
e
s
t

t

o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3

Local Coherence and Ungrammaticality

Paape, Vasishth, Engbert

Annual Meeting of the Association for Computational Linguistics:
Human Language Technologies (pp. 1055–1065). Association for
Computational Linguistics.

Levy, R., Bicknell, K., Slattery, T., & Rayner, K. (2009). Eye move-
ment evidence that readers maintain and act on uncertainty about
past linguistic input. Proceedings of the National Academy of
les sciences, 106(50), 21086–21090. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas
.0907664106, PubMed: 19965371

Lewandowski, D., Kurowicka, D., & Joe, H. (2009). Generating random
correlation matrices based on vines and extended onion method.
Journal of Multivariate Analysis, 100(9), 1989–2001. https://doi.org
/10.1016/j.jmva.2009.04.008

Logac(cid:1)ev, P., & Vasishth, S. (2013). em2: A package for computing
reading time measures for psycholinguistics [Computer software
manual] (R package version 0.9). https://CRAN.R-project.org
/package=em2. CRAN-R.

McKoon, G., & Ratcliff, R.. (2003). Meaning through syntax: Language
comprehension and the reduced relative clause construction.
Psychological Review, 110(3), 490–525. https://doi.org/10.1037
/0033-295X.110.3.490, PubMed: 12885112

Meng, X.-L., & Wong, W. H. (1996). Simulating ratios of normalizing
constants via a simple identity: A theoretical exploration. Statistica
Sinica, 6, 831–860.

Meseguer, E., Carreiras, M., & Clifton, C. (2002). Overt reanalysis
strategies and eye movements during the reading of mild garden
path sentences. Mémoire & Cognition, 30(4), 551–561. https://est ce que je
.org/10.3758/BF03194956, PubMed: 12184556

Mitchell, D. C., Shen, X., Vert, M.. J., & Hodgson, T. L. (2008).
Accounting for regressive eye-movements in models of sentence
traitement: A reappraisal of the selective reanalysis hypothesis.
Journal of Memory and Language, 59(3), 266–293. https://doi.org
.org/10.1016/j.jml.2008.06.002

Morgan, E., Keller, F., & Steedman, M.. (2010). A bottom-up parsing
model of local coherence effects. In S. Ohlsson & R.. Catrambone
(Éd.), Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science
Society (pp. 1559–1564).

Müller, H., & Konieczny, L. (2019, March 29–31). The effect of
context on local syntactic coherence processing [Poster]. 32nd
Annual CUNY Conference on Human Sentence Processing.
University of Colorado Boulder.

Paape, D., & Vasishth, S. (2016). Local coherence and preemptive
digging-in effects in German. Language and Speech, 59(3), 387–403.
https://doi.org/10.1177/0023830915608410, PubMed: 29924534
R Core Team. (2019). R.: A language and environment for statistical
computing [Computer software manual]. https://www.R-project.org.
Raftery, UN. E. (1995). Bayesian model selection in social research.
Sociological Methodology, 25, 111–163. https://doi.org/10.2307
/271063

Rayner, K. (2009). Eye movements and attention in reading, scène
perception, and visual search. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental
Psychologie, 62(8), 1457–1506. https://est ce que je.org/10.1080
/17470210902816461, PubMed: 19449261

Rouder, J.. N. (2005). Are unshifted distributional models appro-
priate for response time? Psychometrika, 70(2), 377–381. https://
doi.org/10.1007/s11336-005-1297-7

Forgeron, G. (2018). A theory of timing effects in a self-organizing
model of sentence processing (Unpublished doctoral dissertation).
University of Connecticut.

Forgeron, G., Franck, J., & Tabor, W. (2018). A self-organizing approach
to subject–verb number agreement. Sciences cognitives, 42(S4),
1043–1074. https://doi.org/10.1111/cogs.12591, PubMed:
29388256

Sturt, P., Pickering, M.. J., & Crocker, M.. W. (1999). Structural
change and reanalysis difficulty in language comprehension.
Journal of Memory and Language, 40(1), 136–150. https://doi.org
.org/10.1006/jmla.1998.2606

Tabor, W., Galantucci, B., & Richardson, D. (2004). Effects of merely
local syntactic coherence on sentence processing. Journal de
Memory and Language, 50(4), 355–370. https://est ce que je.org/10.1016
/j.jml.2004.01.001

Tabor, W., & Hutchins, S. (2004). Evidence for self-organized sen-
tence processing: Digging-in effects. Journal d'expérimentation
Psychologie: Apprentissage, Mémoire, et cognitif, 30(2), 431–450.
https://doi.org/10.1037/0278-7393.30.2.431, PubMed:
14979816

van Schijndel, M., & Linzen, T. (2018). Modeling garden path effects
without explicit hierarchical syntax. In T. Rogers, M.. Rau, J.. Zhu,
& C. Kalish (Éd.), Proceedings of the 40th Annual Conference of
the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 2600–2605). Cognitive
Science Society.

Vasishth, S. (2018, Avril 8). The relationship between paired t-tests
and linear mixed models in a 2 × 2 repeated measures design.
https://vasishth-statistics.blogspot.com/2018/04/the-relationship
-between-paired-t-tests.html.

Villata, S., & Franck, J.. (2020). Similarity-based interference in
agreement comprehension and production: Evidence from object
agreement. Journal de psychologie expérimentale: Apprentissage,
Mémoire, et cognitif, 46(1), 170–188. https://est ce que je.org/10
.1037/xlm0000718, PubMed: 31033310

von der Malsburg, T., & Vasishth, S. (2011). What is the scanpath
signature of syntactic reanalysis? Journal of Memory and Language,
65(2), 109–127. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jml.2011.02.004

von der Malsburg, T., & Vasishth, S. (2013). Scanpaths reveal syn-
tactic underspecification and reanalysis strategies. Language and
Cognitive Processes, 28(10), 1545–1578. https://est ce que je.org/10.1080
/01690965.2012.728232

Vosse, T., & Kempen, G. (2000). Syntactic structure assembly in
human parsing: A computational model based on competitive in-
hibition and a lexicalist grammar. Cognition, 75(2), 105–143.
https://doi.org/10.1016/S0010-0277(00)00063-9, PubMed:
10771275

Westfall, J.. (2015). Follow-up: What about Uri’s 2n rule? https://
jakewestfall.org/ blog/index.php/2015/05/27/follow-up-what
-about-uris-2n-rule.

OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science

58

je

D
o
w
n
o
un
d
e
d

F
r
o
m
h

t
t

p

:
/
/

d
je
r
e
c
t
.

m

je
t
.

/

e
d
toi
o
p
m

je
/

je

un
r
t
je
c
e

p
d

F
/

d
o

je
/

je

/

.

/

1
0
1
1
6
2
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
1
9
2
8
2
5
7
o
p
m
_
un
_
0
0
0
4
1
p
d

/

.

je

F

b
oui
g
toi
e
s
t

t

o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3REPORT image
REPORT image
REPORT image

Télécharger le PDF