What is Life—in Everyday
Understanding? A Focus Group
Study on Lay Perspectives on the
Term Life
Wolfgang Kerbe*
Johannes Kepler University, Linz
and
Biofaction KG, Vienna
Keywords
Focus groups, naive biology, life, everyday
knowledge, synthetic biology
Abstract The philosophical and scientific debate about definitions of
life-as-we-know-it and its value is very diverse. How do non-biologists
characterize these issues? We held focus groups to shed light on the
role of the term life in laypeopleʼs understanding. Results show that
features of early childhood cognition dominate the understanding of the
term life even in adulthood. Textbook knowledge and definitions
derived from specific knowledge systems and beliefs are of minor
importance. For an ethical differentiation between life forms the ability
to feel and to suffer is seen as the crucial criterion. We conclude that
lay perspectives on the concept of life can shape a normative discourse
on existing as well as on new life forms in a crucial way. In addition,
these perspectives may also strongly influence the expectations
towards the life-as-it-could-be that is brought forward by the artificial life
community. While some concepts like metabolism exist both in scientific
and in everyday reasoning as criteria for life, the normative discussion
on life is dominated by such ideas as a hierarchical order of living kinds,
which emphasize “easy to think” concepts of a moral differentiation.
These can also form a basis for the moral standing of artificial life.
1 Introduction
What is life? On the journey from life-as-we-know-it to the life-as-it-could-be, it is not only the question of the
destination that remains open and evolving. What is the starting point? One might argue that biological
literature is a solid basis on which to set out for this endeavor. However, societal and ethical implications
demand a broader horizon. Common knowledge and non-scientific approaches towards life merge with
scientific knowledge and expertise in the public sphere. To be able to engage with the public in a mean-
ingful way, another starting point must be taken into account: lay perspectives on the term life.1
* Johannes Kepler University, Linz, Austria; Biofaction KG, Vienna; Baumbachstraße 10 A-4020, Linz, Austria. E-mail: wkerbe@gmx.at
1 Talking about life can already be a semantic problem. To define life the way we use it throughout the article we follow the Merriam Webster
Online Dictionary. According to their definition life is: “a: the quality that distinguishes a vital and functional being from a dead body, b: a
principle or force that is considered to underlie the distinctive quality of animate beings or c: an organismic state characterized by capacity
for metabolism, growth, reaction to stimuli, and reproduction.” (Life. In Merriam-Webster.com. Merriam-Webster, n.d. Retrieved 17 Oct.
2014. http://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/life.) We have to modify c, because it already gives a list definition of properties of living
entities that is characteristic of scientific accounts of life. We therefore suggest: “an organismic state that encompasses certain properties
that define a living entity.” However, we want to exclude other meanings of life from the discussion (such as life span, biography, or
livelihood) that can be found in the dictionary.
© 2016 Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Artificial Life 22: 119–133 (2016) doi:10.1162/ARTL_a_00181
Published under a Creative Commons Attribution
3.0 Unported (CC BY 3.0) license.
l
D
o
w
n
o
a
d
e
d
f
r
o
m
h
t
t
p
:
/
/
d
i
r
e
c
t
.
m
i
t
.
e
d
u
a
r
t
l
/
/
l
a
r
t
i
c
e
–
p
d
f
/
/
/
/
2
2
1
1
1
9
1
6
6
5
2
4
9
a
r
t
l
/
_
a
_
0
0
1
8
1
p
d
.
f
b
y
g
u
e
s
t
t
o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3
W. Kerbe
What is Life—in Everyday Understanding?
Again: What is life?2 Some philosophers have argued that this might be an impossible or pointless
question to ask [24]. However, in the age of synthetic biology3 with its several facets of dealing with
living organisms, the question gets new meaning. From protocell research to advanced techniques of
metabolic engineering, the notion of life as a toolbox gains momentum [5].
In biology, life is defined by traits (or markers): for example, transformation, autopoeisis, metab-
olism, homeostasis, genome, reproduction, evolution, and interaction with the environment [5].
Other definitions encompass “seven pillars of life”: program, improvization, compartmentalization,
energy, regeneration, adaptability, and seclusion [19]. Toepfer [30, pp. 164–170] offers a whole
historical table of such list definitions, including those by such prominent scientists as Haeckel,
Crick, and Mayr; his own approach to the definition of life includes organization, regulation, and
evolution. Furthermore, there are non-scientific understandings of life [6], as for instance in phil-
osophic traditions [3, 32] and religions. Synthetic biology as a new emerging technoscience brings
new perspectives on life into this discussion.4
But what about public opinion, what about commonsense approaches to life? Previous research
about living kinds has linked anthropological studies of folk biology and developmental studies in
the field of naive biology [13]. Laypeople all over the world, as well as children, categorize objects
into four categories: humans, nonhuman animals, plants, and inanimate objects [2]. Furthermore,
informal biology relies on intuitive modes of understanding. This encompasses forms of vitalism
as conceptual principles of life [15, 17].
The key motivation for investigating naive biology as a case study in developmental psychol-
ogy is to test assumptions about the development of concepts in children. Authors who spe-
cialize in these questions have tried to refine the Piagetian theory of development by showing
that processes and products of knowledge construction are domain-specific (e.g., naive psychology,
physics, and biology), theory-like even in early childhood, and cognitively and socioculturally
constrained [16].
In an earlier study Hatano et al. [12] measured the percentage of children at ages 6, 8, and 10 who
are able to classify 16 living and nonliving entities correctly into the following categories: alive,
having animal properties, sensory properties, and all-living-things properties. The accuracy is rather
high even with 6-year-olds (85% aggregated accuracy across all object and property clusters).
2 Many efforts have been undertaken to answer this question. A few examples from scientific literature are listed here: Schrödinger, E.
(1944). What is life? The physical aspect of the living cell. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Margulis, L., & Sagan, D. (1995).
What is life? New York: Simon & Schuster. Murphy, M. P., & OʼNeill, L. A. J., (1995). What is life? The next fifty years: Speculations on the
future of biology. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Palyi, G., Zucchi, C., & Caglioti, L. (2002). Fundamentals of life. Elsevier.
Luisi, P. L. (2006). The emergence of life: From chemical origins to synthetic biology. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Regis, E.
(2008). What is life? Investigating the nature of life in the age of synthetic biology. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Dabrock, P., Bölker,
M., Braun, M., & Ried, J. (Eds.) (2011). Was ist Leben—im Zeitalter seiner technischen Machbarkeit? Beiträge zur Ethik der synthetischen
Biologie. Freiburg: Karl Alber.
3 Schmidt et al. [29] give the following definition of synthetic biology:
Synthetic biology is the design and construction of new biological systems not found in nature. Synthetic
biology as a scientific label currently includes the following subfields: (A) Engineering DNA-based biological
circuits, including but not limited to standardized biological parts; (B) Defining a minimal genome/minimal
life (top-down); (C) Constructing protocells, i.e. living cells, from scratch (bottom-up); (D) Creating
orthogonal biological systems based on a biochemistry not found in nature, e.g. non-ATGC DNA bases
or non-DNA non-RNA nucleic acids, so called XNA (xenonucleic acid) [. . .] Also relevant to synthetic
biology is a supporting technology, the chemical synthesis of DNA. [29, p. 1]
4 Depending on the different branches of synthetic biology, different aspects of life are in the focus of consideration. In the engineering
approach to construct new biological circuits, the new life is supposed to provide well-designed and -defined metabolic pathways. In the
top-down approach the new organisms need merely live, sustained by the environment in the lab. In the bottom-up approach, new life
should be similar to natural organisms. Finally, orthogonal biological systems provide life that contains a different code and different amino
acids, not to be found in nature [5]. Deplazes-Zemp [5] identifies six modes of dealing with life in synthetic biology: to understand life, to
use life, to minimize and optimize life, to vary life, to overcome life, and to design life. This understanding of life is rather novel and
corresponds to a toolbox approach to life.
120
Artificial Life Volume 22, Number 1
l
D
o
w
n
o
a
d
e
d
f
r
o
m
h
t
t
p
:
/
/
d
i
r
e
c
t
.
m
i
t
.
e
d
u
a
r
t
l
/
/
l
a
r
t
i
c
e
–
p
d
f
/
/
/
/
2
2
1
1
1
9
1
6
6
5
2
4
9
a
r
t
l
/
_
a
_
0
0
1
8
1
p
d
.
f
b
y
g
u
e
s
t
t
o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3
W. Kerbe
What is Life—in Everyday Understanding?
Table 1. Principles of animate-inanimate distinction in infancy [26].
Domain of distinction
Distinction
Categories of distinction
Physical
Onset of motion
Self-propelled versus caused motion
Line of trajectory
Smooth versus irregular
Form of causal action
Action at a distance versus action from contact
Pattern of interaction
Contingent versus non-contingent
Type of causal role
Agent versus recipient
Psychological
Purpose of action
Goal-directed versus without aim
Influence of mental states
Intentional versus accidental
Nevertheless, their data show that children have more difficulty with the abstract concept of alive
than with the more concrete properties of animals, plants, and other living things.
However, Leddon et al. [21] question the methodology of previous studies that used the term
alive to test childrenʼs understanding of biological concepts. In English the word alive is ambiguous
and includes properties of motion, animistic properties, and animal properties in its meaning. In two
experiments they show that using a clearer category like living thing helps children to classify living
entities in the biological sense in a more successful way.
In addition to the living-nonliving boundary, the classification animate-inanimate has been subject
to diverse investigations in developmental psychology. After discussing theories on the emergence
of the animate-inanimate distinction in infancy [9, 22, 25, 26], Rakison and Poulin-Dubois [27] offer
their own list of principles for this differentiation (Table 1).
The development of distinctions along these lines shows that the animate-inanimate distinction is
not an all-or-one phenomenon even with respect to cognitive abilities in infancy. Another aspect of
childrenʼs judgments about living entities is anthropomorphic reasoning. Rigney and Callanan [28]
conclude from their studies on parent-child conversations about animals that anthropomorphism is a
learned way of thinking about animals.
Research on adult populations on the living-nonliving and on the animate-inanimate distinction
is a rare endeavor. The distinction between animate and inanimate entities is one of the final object
distinctions made by Alzheimerʼs patients [14]. A study on the correlation of paranormal beliefs
with confusion of core knowledge domains showed that many undergraduate students do not
judge the living-nonliving or the animate-inanimate distinction according to scientific principles
[23]. Recent findings in neuropsychology show that there are specific brain domains reserved
for the processing of animate and inanimate objects, and even domains that are reserved for an-
imate categories such as similarly behaving animals [4]. This indicates that animate-inanimate dis-
tinctions are fundamental elements of human cognition, and “plausibly part of our evolutionary
heritage” [1].
Goldberg and Thompson-Schill [10] have focused their research on a later stage of cognitive
development as regards the living-nonliving boundary. They have shown that the biological
knowledge of adults is rooted in childhood categorization concepts. These are just partially over-
written by conceptual changes in adulthood (e.g., those present in the knowledge of university
professors).
In contrast to these mainly experimental research traditions, we have chosen an explorative,
qualitative approach to analyze the everyday understanding of life, the living-nonliving boundary, and
Artificial Life Volume 22, Number 1
121
l
D
o
w
n
o
a
d
e
d
f
r
o
m
h
t
t
p
:
/
/
d
i
r
e
c
t
.
m
i
t
.
e
d
u
a
r
t
l
/
/
l
a
r
t
i
c
e
–
p
d
f
/
/
/
/
2
2
1
1
1
9
1
6
6
5
2
4
9
a
r
t
l
/
_
a
_
0
0
1
8
1
p
d
.
f
b
y
g
u
e
s
t
t
o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3
W. Kerbe
What is Life—in Everyday Understanding?
peopleʼs way of differentiating between major categories of living beings. On the one hand, this
approach should contribute to the findings of the previous studies in that it uses an adult sample.
On the other hand, it should be a starting point for more quantitative work on adultsʼ concepts of
the living as well as for the elaboration of a social representation5 of life. By choosing such an
approach we make ourselves open to any kind of interpretation of living-nonliving boundaries
instead of distinguishing a right scientific from a wrong non-scientific point of view. On the con-
trary, laypeopleʼs assumptions about life can be seen as embedded in the cultural system of com-
mon sense [8]. The principles of commonsense thinking are different from scientific reasoning in
that different demands for validity are relevant and that different functions have to be fulfilled (e.g.,
objectivity versus the ability to communicate). For a differentiated discussion on this matter see
Wagner and Hayes [31].
The present study was designed to answer the following questions: (1) What defines the term life
in the understanding of non-experts? (2) How would laypeople differentiate between major catego-
ries of life forms? And (3) how do people make distinctions between life forms with respect to
norms and values? We mean to give a first insight into the cognitive and evaluative dimensions
of a social representation of the biological term life.
2 Method
2.1 Participants
We carried out a total of nine interviews, six focus group discussions, and one larger group discus-
sion in a focus-group-like setting. The total number of participants was 49, including the interviews.
The age of the participants ranged from 20 to 70 (M = 40.5, SD = 14.2).
The interview partners and the participants in one focus group discussion were undergraduate
students from Linz University. The other focus group discussions were held with groups with di-
verse backgrounds: people from a wholesale company, students from a private Catholic university, a
group with a strong relation to novel technology, members of a Catholic menʼs association, and a
group with strong links to the esoteric scene. The larger group discussion was organized by a Cath-
olic parish. Participation was compensated at A10 per person-hour.
The groups were selected with respect to three variables: education, supportiveness for tech-
nology, and religious belief (Table 2). Education was measured on an ordinal scale from 0 to 7
(see Appendix 1) where 0 meant no formal education and 7 meant a Ph.D. Supportiveness for
technology was measured using items from Special Eurobarometer 341 (QB1–QB7, slightly mod-
ified; see Appendix 2) on biotechnology [7]. However, the attempt to classify the groups using these
items failed due to the large number of “donʼt know” answers. Religious belief was assessed with
the item “Do you believe in God?” on a 5-point Likert scale. The means of the groups are given in
Table 2.
While the choice of education as a sampling criterion seems obvious (corresponding to different
levels of biological textbook knowledge), the other two criteria need further explication. Both were
used simply because the value-laden, normative aspects of the understanding of life were expected
to vary across these dimensions.
5 Social representations can be defined by structural features (content ), by dynamic characteristics ( process), and by their epistemic
implications. The first definition regards social representations as individual knowledge systems: Social representations are a “struc-
tured, cognitive, affective, evaluative and operative, metaphorical or iconic ‘portrayal’ of socially relevant phenomena. These can be
‘events’, ‘stimuli’ or ‘facts’ of which individuals are potentially aware and which are shared by other members of the social group. This
commonality between people represents a fundamental element of the social identity of the individual” [30, p. 120]. Secondly, when
viewed as a process, social representations concern the origin, change, and elaboration of the above-mentioned constructs. Thirdly,
social representations function as a kind of macro reduction in cognitive theory, allowing the cross-analysis of different levels (macro-
micro relation) [30]. In the tradition of social representations research, different categories of phenomena were the objects of inves-
tigation: (a ) popularized science, (b) social structures and political events, (c ) cultural objects [30].
122
Artificial Life Volume 22, Number 1
l
D
o
w
n
o
a
d
e
d
f
r
o
m
h
t
t
p
:
/
/
d
i
r
e
c
t
.
m
i
t
.
e
d
u
a
r
t
l
/
/
l
a
r
t
i
c
e
–
p
d
f
/
/
/
/
2
2
1
1
1
9
1
6
6
5
2
4
9
a
r
t
l
/
_
a
_
0
0
1
8
1
p
d
.
f
b
y
g
u
e
s
t
t
o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3
W. Kerbe
What is Life—in Everyday Understanding?
Table 2. Description of the sample regarding the selection criteria education and religious belief.
Group description
Students (including interviews)
Company
Esoteric group
Catholic university
Tech group
Catholic parish groups
n
14
7
6
5
6
11
Education, Mdn
Religious belief, M (SD)
4
3
5.5
6
6
5
1.55 (SD = 1.57)
2.29 (SD = 0.95)
2.60 (SD = 0.55)
4.00 (SD = 0)
1.17 (SD = 1.17)
3.00 (SD = 0.82)
Note: Education is given as the median on an ordinal 8-point scale. Religious belief is given as the mean on a 5-point
Likert scale.
2.2 Procedure
Groups were informed, when they were recruited, that they would be involved in a group discussion
on synthetic biology. At the beginning of the interviews and focus group sessions, participants were
presented with a stone. The interviewer or moderator let them identify the item as a stone and then
insisted that the stone was alive. The participants had to argue why they thought whether the stone
was alive or not alive (definition of life) and how they would differentiate between different forms of
life (category differentiation). Then the participants were confronted with value-laden questions re-
garding life, namely, why they think killing humans is forbidden in many cultures whereas killing
nonhuman organisms is less dramatized. In addition, they were asked what they thought about
the manipulation of genetic information within different organisms (moral differentiation). After
the discussions and interviews, participants had to fill in a short questionnaire about age, gender,
items on supportiveness towards technologies, religious and ideological background, and level of
education. Finally, the participants were debriefed.
2.3 Additional Data
In addition to the interview and focus group material, transcripts from a former focus group study
[20] were added to the data corpus. In these discussions about newspaper articles on synthetic bi-
ology the definition and moral status of life were discussed at some points. This data was not used
for analyzing the mere definition of life, but for investigating on the differentiation between life
forms.
3 Results
The interviews and discussions (in German) were recorded between March 2012 and February 2013
and transcribed verbatim. (The quotations in this section are translations.) The data corpus consisted
of these transcripts and of paraphrased transcripts from the COSY study [20]. With the help of
QDA software, Atlas.ti open coding and memo strategies from grounded theory were applied.
The units of analysis were thematic units. The resulting codes were structured according to the re-
search questions (definition, category differentiation, and moral differentiation).
3.1 What Defines the Biological Term Life in the Lay Perspective?
An overview of the answer to this question is given in Table 3. The categories are discussed in more
detail below, in the order of their frequency of occurrence in the data corpus. Furthermore, exem-
plary quotations from the interviews and discussions are given there.
Artificial Life Volume 22, Number 1
123
l
D
o
w
n
o
a
d
e
d
f
r
o
m
h
t
t
p
:
/
/
d
i
r
e
c
t
.
m
i
t
.
e
d
u
a
r
t
l
/
/
l
a
r
t
i
c
e
–
p
d
f
/
/
/
/
2
2
1
1
1
9
1
6
6
5
2
4
9
a
r
t
l
/
_
a
_
0
0
1
8
1
p
d
.
f
b
y
g
u
e
s
t
t
o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3
W. Kerbe
What is Life—in Everyday Understanding?
Table 3. Quotation count of criteria for the definition of life in laypeopleʼs understanding.
Criterion
Motion
Change
Growth
Metabolism
Soul
Subject to death
Emergence
Consciousness
Inner architecture
Interaction
Respiration
Activity
Energy
Genes
Autonomy
Duration
Transformation of energy
Adaptation
Communication
Gaia
No repetitions
Life force
Evolution
Inner driving force
Number of quotations (number of groups)
24 (5)
18 (5)
18 (5)
12 (4)
8 (3)
7 (4)
7 (4)
6 (3)
6 (2)
6 (2)
6 (3)
5 (2)
4 (2)
4 (2)
3 (2)
3 (3)
3 (2)
2 (1)
2 (2)
2 (2)
2 (1)
2 (2)
1 (1)
1 (1)
Note: The quotations were counted in the whole data corpus including
interviews and focus groups. Numbers in brackets represent the number
of groups (see Table 2) in which the quotations were found.
124
Artificial Life Volume 22, Number 1
l
D
o
w
n
o
a
d
e
d
f
r
o
m
h
t
t
p
:
/
/
d
i
r
e
c
t
.
m
i
t
.
e
d
u
a
r
t
l
/
/
l
a
r
t
i
c
e
–
p
d
f
/
/
/
/
2
2
1
1
1
9
1
6
6
5
2
4
9
a
r
t
l
/
_
a
_
0
0
1
8
1
p
d
.
f
b
y
g
u
e
s
t
t
o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3
W. Kerbe
What is Life—in Everyday Understanding?
The ability to move is most frequently and spontaneously given as a defining property of living entities:
Quotation 1.
obviously cannot even move, because it is rigid, static, yes.”
“Because (LAUGHTER) life for me is with, why not, that is a good question, because it
This implies that objects that do not move are not alive (e.g., plants), whereas any moving object
would be (e.g., cars or other moving artefacts). However, the absence of motion is a salient property
of the stone that was presented to the participants. It would be interesting to see if other objects
(a self-propelled car model, a plant, a seed, a flame) would produce similar reactions.
Motion as a characteristic of living entities is a concept that we acquire at a very early stage of
development. The fact that this comes spontaneously, in interviews and focus groups, to define life
shows that this mode of categorization is not completely overwritten by definitions of life according
to the traits learned at school or at university. Moreover, the prototypic life forms that we have in
our minds are human beings and animals whose ability to move is obvious to us.
Participants often emphasize that the living thing must be able to move by itself and not by an external
force. However, they attribute liveliness to inanimate objects that are moved by the wind or, as the stone,
over the course of millions of years. One participant even classified movement on an atomic level as life.
In the esoteric group motion was also mentioned in connection with the presence of an astral
body. This presence, they say, can be seen in the animal kingdom. Associating motion with a non-
material property could be interpreted as an “essence of motion.”
The second fact that people recognize as an important trait is that living things undergo changes.
“But if there is a change of form, this is actually a life somehow, maybe not in a way, that
Quotation 2.
we can be aware of it, because our senses cannot capture it, because we donʼt have the time, but if (there
is) a change of form, this happens over a long time span, so there must be something that is alive.”
The definition by change includes plants in the realm of the living. Participants argue that this change, as
well as the above-mentioned motion, must be something intrinsic to the living object. External changes
like corrosion or degradation are excluded from this definition. However, some participants see change
in general as a trait of living things and therefore ascribe life status to the stone as well. They say that a
change of form can happen over a long period of time and hence can be invisible.
Growth and development are also important in laypeopleʼs understanding of life.
Quotation 3.
develops, that it grows, that it so to speak develops further.”
“From my point of view a stone is not alive, because we relate life to, that something
Growth is an aspect of life that preschool children are already familiar with. In fact, some of the
participants did not exclude the stone from the group of living entities, because they attribute
growth to crystals, mountains, or “mother earth.”
The three most prominent definitions of life in the data corpus are motion, change, and growth/
development. The two categories growth and change are also closely related to each other. These
three aspects have in common that they are perceivable by vision (although sometimes over a longer
period of time). Furthermore change, growth, and movement are elements of preschool childrenʼs
cognition of living kinds [16, 27].
Metabolism is another property of living entities frequently mentioned by the participants.
Quotation 4.
“For me there must be some process involved, some sort of metabolism, or whatever.”
This metabolism is sometimes described implicitly:
Quotation 5.
know, the stone doesnʼt do that.”
“Especially bacteria take up something, somehow, and excrete something, I donʼt
Artificial Life Volume 22, Number 1
125
l
D
o
w
n
o
a
d
e
d
f
r
o
m
h
t
t
p
:
/
/
d
i
r
e
c
t
.
m
i
t
.
e
d
u
a
r
t
l
/
/
l
a
r
t
i
c
e
–
p
d
f
/
/
/
/
2
2
1
1
1
9
1
6
6
5
2
4
9
a
r
t
l
/
_
a
_
0
0
1
8
1
p
d
.
f
b
y
g
u
e
s
t
t
o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3
W. Kerbe
What is Life—in Everyday Understanding?
Metabolism is a concept that children seem to acquire at school. It is not as obvious as the concepts
above when considering plants, whereas animals and human beings visibly eat and excrete substances.
The notion of a soul for the definition of life did not come up in the Christian groups that would
attribute a soul only to human beings. It was mentioned in the student and esoteric groups.
In some cases life was defined as being subject to death. This may seem a simple antonymic defi-
nition, but it actually formulates life as a state, which a living entity can lose, turning into dead matter.
Although an important criterion for the differentiation between classes of living entities (see
below), the possession of consciousness served also as defining motive for life in general. Partici-
pants occasionally mentioned that it is hard to tell, in spite of scientific methods, if an object has
consciousness or not.
Life was also defined in terms of emergence: Participants said that life is more than the sum of
the parts of an organism.
A characteristic described by the interviewees was the inner architecture of organisms (for in-
stance, being composed of cells).
Quotation 6.
of their inner architecture.”
“Yes you would say that also in biology, that they (single-cell organisms) live, because
This is a definition that comes close to modern scientific characterizations of life that are rooted in a
mechanistic or materialistic view of life.
According to the participants, living organisms interact with the environment. This can be inter-
preted as a more general notion, which encompasses metabolism and motion and the more specific
term respiration, which was also a defining criterion for some participants.
Activity, as a defining criterion for life, can also be seen as an umbrella term for motion, change,
metabolism, respiration, and others. It clearly draws the boundary between the living and the stone,
which has the outer appearance of being passive and only moved or changed by outer forces.
In spite of the ongoing discussions in the media and the life sciences, the possession of genes was
only mentioned in two groups (the student and the tech group).
In two groups the notion of energy was associated with life, meant more in an esoteric than in the
physical sense.
Living entities were also described as autonomous.
The term duration in connection with life means that some participants emphasized the observable
time scale in which processes of life happen, in contrast to geological time.
Transformation of energy (in the physical sense), adaptation to the environment, communication,
and the ability to evolve were named as further defining elements of life.
In two cases the Gaia hypothesis was mentioned, which attributes the status of life to the whole
ecosystem of the planet Earth.
One group declared the absence of repetitions as a property of living systems.
The presence of a life force (vis vitae) in living entities was mentioned twice. One participant also
attributed a more physical inner driving force to living things.
Comparing the data with biological textbook definitions [5, 19, 30] one can find traits in the latter
that are completely absent from everyday understanding. These are processes for the organization of
systems, stability, interdependence of parts, autopoeisis, chemical uniqueness, improvisation, com-
partmentalization, regeneration, and seclusion, to name but a few.
3.1.1 Group-Specific Definitions
The esoteric group was the only group that did not use growth as a defining criterion for life. This
group also stated that there is no repetition in living entities, meaning that continuous change con-
nected to individuality is an important characteristic, while it was the only group that did not use
mere change as a defining trait. (The absence of repetition implies change, whereas change does not
imply the absence of repetition.) People from the Catholic university were the only ones to describe
life as a material inner driving force.
126
Artificial Life Volume 22, Number 1
l
D
o
w
n
o
a
d
e
d
f
r
o
m
h
t
t
p
:
/
/
d
i
r
e
c
t
.
m
i
t
.
e
d
u
a
r
t
l
/
/
l
a
r
t
i
c
e
–
p
d
f
/
/
/
/
2
2
1
1
1
9
1
6
6
5
2
4
9
a
r
t
l
/
_
a
_
0
0
1
8
1
p
d
.
f
b
y
g
u
e
s
t
t
o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3
W. Kerbe
What is Life—in Everyday Understanding?
Evolution was only mentioned by the tech group. This group had also the highest number of
different defining items per participant. Students were the only ones to mention the adaptation to
the environment as essential for living beings. The criterion for life that they quoted most often was
absent in the discussion of the church parish groups.
We found the lowest diversity of characteristics in the company and the Catholic university
groups (6 each), and the highest in the tech group (16) and the student group (18).
3.1.2 Classification of Definitions
Participantsʼ definitions can be further classified in the following categories: traits that are easily
perceivable with our senses (sensory), traits that are abstract, process-like concepts, and traits that can
mainly be observed using scientific apparatus. (See Table 4.) This categorization shows the dominance
of easily perceivable traits relative to the other classes of definitions in everyday understanding of the
biological term life.
3.2 How Do Laypeople Differentiate between Major Categories of Life Forms?
The main criterion of differentiation between major categories (humans, nonhuman animals, plants,
microorganisms, and inanimate objects) that participants referred to was consciousness, intelligence,
mind, the ability to think, or the possession of a brain.
“OK. The bird is a being with a brain, with a real distinctive brain so to speak. It directs
Quotation 7.
everything with it. The tree is also a living object, because it changes and changes by itself, but not
consciously but simply by environmental influences, weather and seasons. That is the difference: brain
and no brain.”
“So I would say, finally everything can be put down to consciousness, and man is in
Quotation 8.
this, if you see it like this, in the highest order, if you like, because he has self-consciousness, because
he is self-conscious.”
Quotation 9.
(humans, animals) from things.”
“That really is for me the possibility to think that distinguishes these two kinds of life
This may be a representation of anthropomorphizing reasoning that takes human beings as
a prototype for life. Nonetheless, the attribution of a consciousness as a trait of living
organisms, albeit rather rudimentary when concerning microorganisms, can be found in
philosophical literature (e.g., [3]). A consequence is that a basic differentiation between ar-
tefacts, plants, animals, and human beings is also possible along these lines.
The second prominent feature for differentiation was inner architecture, the composition of the
organisms. Less important criteria were adaptation to the environment, similarity to human beings,
language, and the use of tools. In the esoteric group the possession or absence of certain bodies
(astral body, mental body) served as classification methodology.
These categorization strategies have in common that they use rather abstract concepts in contrast
to the mere definition of life. It is hard to perceive consciousness, inner architecture, adaptation, and
astral bodies with the sensory apparatus. Motion, growth, and change, on the other hand, are more
directly linked to perceptions, and are therefore less abstract concepts.
3.3 How Do Laypeople Differentiate between Life Forms with Respect to
Norms and Values?
The most important trait for normative differentiation between living entities was their ability to
have feelings, to feel pain, or to be able to suffer.
Artificial Life Volume 22, Number 1
127
l
D
o
w
n
o
a
d
e
d
f
r
o
m
h
t
t
p
:
/
/
d
i
r
e
c
t
.
m
i
t
.
e
d
u
a
r
t
l
/
/
l
a
r
t
i
c
e
–
p
d
f
/
/
/
/
2
2
1
1
1
9
1
6
6
5
2
4
9
a
r
t
l
/
_
a
_
0
0
1
8
1
p
d
.
f
b
y
g
u
e
s
t
t
o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3
W. Kerbe
What is Life—in Everyday Understanding?
Table 4. Classification of participantsʼ definitions.
Criterion
Motion
Change
Growth
Metabolism
Soul
Subject to death
Emergence
Consciousness
Inner architecture
Interaction
Respiration
Activity
Energy
Genes
Autonomy
Duration
Transformation of energy
Adaptation
Communication
Gaia
No repetitions
Life force
Evolution
Category
Sensory
Sensory
Sensory
Sensory, scientific
Abstract
Antonym
Abstract
Abstract
Scientific
Sensory, scientific
Sensory
Sensory
Abstract
Scientific
Abstract, scientific
Process
Scientific
Process
Sensory, scientific
Abstract
Process
Abstract
Abstract, process
Inner driving force
Scientific
Note: Criteria are listed in the order of their frequency (see Table 3).
128
Artificial Life Volume 22, Number 1
l
D
o
w
n
o
a
d
e
d
f
r
o
m
h
t
t
p
:
/
/
d
i
r
e
c
t
.
m
i
t
.
e
d
u
a
r
t
l
/
/
l
a
r
t
i
c
e
–
p
d
f
/
/
/
/
2
2
1
1
1
9
1
6
6
5
2
4
9
a
r
t
l
/
_
a
_
0
0
1
8
1
p
d
.
f
b
y
g
u
e
s
t
t
o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3
W. Kerbe
What is Life—in Everyday Understanding?
“Exactly, but I donʼt know, if I look at such a thing, at fur farms or the like, then I have
Quotation 10.
pity somehow as a normal human being, or sympathy or something like that because I see that that thing
suffers and if I kill another man, then I also see that he suffers. Therefore I would argue like that.”
“Anyway, a mouse, fish, goat, human, they all feel pain. So a stone, if you like, if I try
Quotation 11.
to smash it with an axe, on my opinion it does not feel that. It does not hurt it. It may be a pity
because the beautiful stone is broken but in principle it does not feel it. But with living things it is
simply that they have feelings. You donʼt know if that changes their brains, if they have pain, or if
they will have any disadvantages in life and that, I think, should not be caused deliberately.”
This is again an anthropomorphizing viewpoint that extends human experiences with suffering to
animals and plants.
There were two interrelated criteria as regards moral differentiation, namely the survival of man
and the food chain. The first was a more anthropocentric argument. Sometimes the two motives
intertwined:
Quotation 12.
to feed ourselves.”
“Because animals have always been in the food chain. We had to kill them to be able
The argument of manʼs place in a food chain reminds one of the old model of the great chain of being.
The argument of the food chain as well as that of the divine order of the great chain of being assume
a hierarchical taxonomic principle. These hierarchical models seem to appeal to a commonsense
mechanism of ordering living entities due to an “easily thinkable” principle and also allow for a
categorization of organisms under normative aspects.
The visibility of the organisms was also important for the judgment of interference, manipulation,
or killing.
“And with human beings, if I kill a human being, and a plant and a bacterium, [. . .]
Quotation 13.
I cannot even see it. [. . .] It all circles around the question what I can perceive as a human being, and
what I cannot perceive.”
This visibility is similar to the sensory-perceivable concepts in the lay definitions mentioned above.
In addition, the remoteness of something invisible to human beings in the hierarchical concepts of
the food chain and the great chain of being is obvious and therefore tends to exclude these entities
from ethical considerations.
As has been mentioned above, the notion of consciousness served as a defining trait of living
entities and as a general differentiation criterion. However, consciousness or the possession of a
brain was also helpful for making ethical differences between life forms.
“If I copy the material, I do not have that, but so to speak, the more stupid an organism
Quotation 14.
is, the less we care if we interfere with its genome, so in other words this is the case with any kind of
bacteria.”
For genetic manipulation people differentiated between contained (for instance in laboratories) and
uncontained organisms. This stems from a general risk perception of organisms, rather than from
their intrinsic value.
There was also the argument that there is a sanctity or value of life for any kind of living organ-
ism. Therefore these entities should be seen as morally considerable. This follows the assumptions
and belief systems of some Indian and African philosophies [3] and also the general concept of
biocentric thinking [11].
The attribution of a soul was important for some groups for moral differentiation. In philoso-
phy this goes back as far as Aristotle and culminates in medieval mysticism. In the participantsʼ
Artificial Life Volume 22, Number 1
129
l
D
o
w
n
o
a
d
e
d
f
r
o
m
h
t
t
p
:
/
/
d
i
r
e
c
t
.
m
i
t
.
e
d
u
a
r
t
l
/
/
l
a
r
t
i
c
e
–
p
d
f
/
/
/
/
2
2
1
1
1
9
1
6
6
5
2
4
9
a
r
t
l
/
_
a
_
0
0
1
8
1
p
d
.
f
b
y
g
u
e
s
t
t
o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3
W. Kerbe
What is Life—in Everyday Understanding?
expressions the soul concept varies from an animistic picture that assumes that all living kinds have a
soul to a more anthropocentric picture, where human beings alone are in the possession of it.
Finally, participants would also differentiate between classes of living things by their cuteness:
You should not kill what you can caress.
4 Conclusions
For the quest to get from the life-as-we-know-it to the life-as-it-could-be, and especially for a rich
discourse on such issues, not only within the scientific community, but also with a wider public,
several conclusions have to be drawn.
First of all, the normative aspects of life have to be taken into account. In everyday understand-
ing, whatever we do to existing living entities and what new entities should be made, and how they
should be treated, normatively depends primarily on the attribution of an ability to suffer. This goes
beyond scientific stimulus-response models and consists of a mere everyday assumption about
which living kinds can suffer and which cannot. This attribution of an ability to suffer will clearly
shape the standing of artificial living entities, too. Although biocentric perspectives widen the range
of moral considerations to all living things, the lay groups shared the opinion of some philosophers
that suffering is the crucial criterion [11].
Secondly, common sense uses hierarchical models such as the food chain, anthropomorphizing
assumptions (a similarity to human beings), and even the great chain of being for structuring the
ethical aspects of life. This may lead to an acceptance of altering existing life or creating new life on
the level of microorganisms, in contrast to severe objections regarding higher organisms (see also
[18]). A question for further research would be, where artificial life would fit into this order. Is sim-
ilarity to existing entities the key criterion for laypeopleʼs judgments? Are the new entities regarded
as mere artefacts, or even regarded as the latest stage of evolution, and valued as such?
Furthermore, a social representation of life or, in other terms, a lay concept emphasizes traits that
are easily perceivable with our senses, whereas abstract concepts like soul or consciousness and traits
that are only measurable with scientific devices such as genes and a cellular inner architecture are less
prominent in the everyday understanding of the living. This is also the case for process-like char-
acteristics such as evolution and adaptation, which are also hard to observe for the non-scientific eye.
The consequence of this reduction to the sensory apparatus for the categorization of artificial life
forms is that to become “real” for laypersons, the new life forms or the consequences of their ex-
istence must be perceivable to them.
However, the structure of the representation of life incorporates scientific as well as non-scientific
concepts. This shows on the one hand that engaging the public on issues of life can build on a
dialogue along the lines of common concepts such as metabolism or evolution. This can easily be
complemented by more scientific education or explanation.
On the other hand, the picture is only complete when non-scientific concepts enter the stage,
such as for instance the notion of a soul, or an assumption of an ability to suffer, which heavily
influence normative aspects of life. These notions inform the laypersonsʼ normative concepts of
how to order the living. Biocentrism or hierarchical models of nature can structure not only how
existing life should be treated but also what the status of new life ought to be. The resulting lay
theories or concepts are “easy to think” and allow for pragmatic action [31].
Finally, we want to draw conclusions from a more psychological perspective, following the lines
of the research tradition in developmental psychology mentioned above. The link between the child-
hood distinction of living and nonliving entities or of animate and inanimate beings and laypeopleʼs
concepts is the aspect of motion. This shows that the understanding of the biological term life from
early childhood cognition still dominates adultsʼ perception of living entities. Other concepts, such
as change and growth, are also already familiar to children below the age of 10.
However, growth and motion can also be found in older biological textbook definitions of
life (see also [30, pp. 164–165]). Metabolism, emergence, the ability to evolve, interaction with
130
Artificial Life Volume 22, Number 1
l
D
o
w
n
o
a
d
e
d
f
r
o
m
h
t
t
p
:
/
/
d
i
r
e
c
t
.
m
i
t
.
e
d
u
a
r
t
l
/
/
l
a
r
t
i
c
e
–
p
d
f
/
/
/
/
2
2
1
1
1
9
1
6
6
5
2
4
9
a
r
t
l
/
_
a
_
0
0
1
8
1
p
d
.
f
b
y
g
u
e
s
t
t
o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3
W. Kerbe
What is Life—in Everyday Understanding?
the environment, and the possession of genes are more examples of textbook knowledge repro-
duced by the participants. This shows that childhood cognition merges with knowledge from later
school socialization to form the cognitive elements of a social representation of life. With the ex-
ception of metabolism, the more modern textbook definitions are scarce within the data corpus.
Although the sample also included Christian and esoteric groups, non-scientific criteria such as
soul, energy (force), a life force, or the Gaia hypothesis were not very prominent. Further quanti-
tative studies can clarify the proportions of the distribution of these concepts in the public sphere.
These findings support the results from Goldberg and Thompson-Schill [10]. The scientific text-
book knowledge from elementary or high-school education only partly overwrites or complements
the categorization regime from early childhood.
Concrete traits, while sufficient for defining life, are not sufficient for a rough classification of
living entities, although they are ideal for folk or lay taxonomy of specific species. When talking
about general categories of living entities, such as human beings, animals, plants, and sometimes
microorganisms, participants referred to more abstract concepts such as consciousness, inner archi-
tecture, and astral bodies. The primary criterion, consciousness, can be seen as a sort of anthropo-
morphizing reasoning.
As our ways of recognizing living entities are so deeply inscribed in our mind, the final test for
artificial life, whatever form it may take, may be presenting it to children or laypeople to see how
they would position it in relation to the existing tree of life.
This study can only contribute to describing the static aspects of a social representation of life
and, with respect to the definition of social representations, only its cognitive and parts of its eval-
uative dimension. As the notion of a soul or that of energy does not seem to be exclusive for
esoteric or Christian groups, new assumptions must be made as regards the group specificity of such
definitions.
One limitation of the study is the overrepresentation of more highly educated members of the
public. The only group that did not have a highly educated background was that of the wholesale
company. This was partly due to the introduction of the discussion in the phase of recruiting partic-
ipants. The topic of synthetic biology was only interesting for people who could at least associate
something with the term or who were not embarrassed to discuss matters they were not familiar with.
Furthermore, the study emphasized contributions by Christian groups. This is due to the assump-
tion that these groups would deal more with ethical questions in the context of life than other
groups, and that they would enrich the findings with more extreme positions. These two points
might distort the picture when trying to generalize the results with respect to a general public.
Further studies in this direction should primarily target the groups that were absent in the present
sample, to obtain a real image of the public understanding of life.
We asked about criteria for differentiation between classes of organisms in general. To do this
more precisely, the classes should be tested two by two: plant versus inanimate object, animal versus
human, and so on. To gain even more precise insights into the positioning of artificial life by lay-
persons, descriptions of existing state-of-the-art examples—in silico or in vitro—could be taken as
stimulus material for the focus group discussions.
Acknowledgment
Wolfgang Kerbe acknowledges the financial support of the project “SYNMOD: Synthetic Biology
to Obtain Novel Antibiotics and Optimized Production Systems” through the Austrian Science
Fund (FWF) grant no. I490-B12.
References
1. Atran, S. (1990). Cognitive foundations of natural history: Towards an anthropology of science. Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press.
2. Atran, S. (1998). Folk biology and the anthropology of science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 21, 597–611.
3. Brenner, A. (2009). Leben. Stuttgart: Reclam.
Artificial Life Volume 22, Number 1
131
l
D
o
w
n
o
a
d
e
d
f
r
o
m
h
t
t
p
:
/
/
d
i
r
e
c
t
.
m
i
t
.
e
d
u
a
r
t
l
/
/
l
a
r
t
i
c
e
–
p
d
f
/
/
/
/
2
2
1
1
1
9
1
6
6
5
2
4
9
a
r
t
l
/
_
a
_
0
0
1
8
1
p
d
.
f
b
y
g
u
e
s
t
t
o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3
W. Kerbe
What is Life—in Everyday Understanding?
4. Connolly, A. C., Guntupalli, J. S., Gors, J., Hanke, M., Halchenko, Y. O., Wu, Y., Abdi, H. V., &
Haxby, J. (2012). The representation of biological classes in the human brain. The Journal of Neuroscience,
32(8), 2608–2618.
5. Deplazes-Zemp, A. (2012). The conception of life in synthetic biology. Science and Engineering Ethics,
18(4), 757–774.
6. Deplazes-Zemp, A., & Biller-Andorno, N. (2012). Explaining life: Synthetic biology and non-scientific
understandings of life. EMBO Reports, 13, 959–963.
7. European Commission (2010). Eurobarometer 73.1 Biotechnology. Available at http://ec.europa.eu/public_
opinion/archives/ebs/ebs_341_en.pdf (accessed January 2014).
8. Geertz, C. (1987). Dichte Beschreibung: Beiträge zum Verstehen kultureller Systeme. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
9. Gelman, R., & Spelke, E. S. (1981). The development of thoughts about animate and inanimate
objects: Implications for research on social cognition. In J. H. Flavell & L. Ross (Eds.), Social Cognition
(pp. 43–66). New York: Academic Press.
10. Goldberg, R. F., & Thompson-Schill, S. L. (2009). Developmental “roots” in mature biological knowledge.
Psychological Science, 20(4), 480–487.
11. Goodpaster, K. E. (1978). On being morally considerable. The Journal of Philosophy, 75(6), 308–325.
12. Hatano, G., Siegler, R. S., Richards, D. D., Inagaki, K., Stavy, R., & Wax, N. (1993). The development
of biological knowledge, a multi-national study. Cognitive Development, 8(1), 47–62.
13. Hatano, G., & Inagaki, K. (1999). A developmental perspective on informal biology. In D. L. Medin
& S. Atran (Eds.), Folkbiology (pp. 321–354). Cambridge, MA, London: MIT Press.
14. Hodges, J. R., Graham, N., & Patterson, K. (1995). Charting the progression of semantic dementia:
Implications for the organisation of semantic memory. Memory, 3, 587–604.
15. Inagaki, K., & Hatano, G. (1993). Young childrenʼs understanding of the mind-body distinction.
Child Development, 64, 1534–1549.
16. Inagaki, K., & Hatano, G. (2002). Young childrenʼs naïve thinking about the biological world. New York, Brighton:
Psychology Press.
17. Inagaki, K., & Hatano, G. (2004). Vitalistic causality on young childrenʼs naïve biology. Trends in Cognitive
Sciences, 8(8), 356–362.
18. Kerbe, W., & Schmidt, M. (2015). Splicing the boundaries: The experiences of bioart exhibition visitors.
Leonardo, 48(2), 128–136.
19. Koshland, D. E., Jr. (2002). The seven pillars of life. Science, 295, 2215–2216.
20. Kronberger, N., Holtz, P., & Wagner, W. (2012). Consequences of media information uptake and
deliberation: Focus groupsʼ symbolic coping with synthetic biology. Public Understanding of Science,
21(2), 174–187.
21. Leddon, E. M., Waxman, S. R., & Medin, D. L. (2008). Unmasking “alive”: Childrenʼs appreciation
of a concept linking all living things. Journal of Cognition and Development, 9(4), 461–473.
22. Leslie, A. M. (1995). A theory of agency. In D. Sperber, D. Premack, & A. J. Premack (Eds.),
Causal Cognition (pp. 121–141). Oxford, UK: Clarendon.
23. Lindeman, M., Svedholm, A. M., Takada, M., Lönnqvist, J., & Verkasalo, M. (2011). Core knowledge
confusions among university students. Science & Education, 20, 439–451. DOI 10.1007/s11191-009-9210-x.
24. Machery, E. (2012). Why I stopped worrying about the definition of life… and why you should as
well. Synthese, 185, 145–164.
25. Mandler, J. M. (1992). How to build a baby: II. Conceptual primitives. Psychological Review, 99,
587–604.
26. Premack, D. (1990). The infantsʼ theory of self-propelled objects. Cognition, 36, 1–16.
27. Rakison, D. H., & Poulin-Dubois, D. (2001). Developmental origin of the animate-inanimate distinction.
Psychological Bulletin, 127(2), 209–228.
28. Rigney, J. C., & Callanan, M. A. (2011). Patterns in parent-child conversations about animals at a marine
science-center. Cognitive Development, 26, 155–171.
132
Artificial Life Volume 22, Number 1
l
D
o
w
n
o
a
d
e
d
f
r
o
m
h
t
t
p
:
/
/
d
i
r
e
c
t
.
m
i
t
.
e
d
u
a
r
t
l
/
/
l
a
r
t
i
c
e
–
p
d
f
/
/
/
/
2
2
1
1
1
9
1
6
6
5
2
4
9
a
r
t
l
/
_
a
_
0
0
1
8
1
p
d
.
f
b
y
g
u
e
s
t
t
o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3
W. Kerbe
What is Life—in Everyday Understanding?
29. Schmidt, M., Ganguli-Mitra, A., Torgersen, H., Kelle, A., Deplazes, A., & Biller-Andorno, N. (2009).
A priority paper for the societal and ethical aspects of synthetic biology. Systems and Synthetic Biology,
3, 3–7.
30. Toepfer, G. (2005). Der Begriff des Lebens. In U. Krohs & G. Toepfer (Eds.), Philosophie der Biologie
(pp. 157–174). Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
31. Wagner, W., & Hayes, N. (2005). Everyday discourse and common sense: The theory of social representations.
Basingstoke, New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
32. Weber, B. (2011). “Life.” In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2011 ed.).
Available at http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2011/entries/life/ (accessed January 2014).
Appendix 1
The education scale was derived from ISCED and from the special properties of the Austrian education
system (see also http://www.statistik.at/web_en/statistics/education_culture/formal_education/
index.html). The scale had these values: 0 = no formal education, 1 = primary school, 2 = secondary
school, 3 = secondary school and vocational training, 4 = secondary school upper level, 5 = bachelor,
6 = master, 7 = Ph.D.
The differentiation between 3 and 4 was made because scientific education is generally more
common in the upper level of secondary schools than in vocational training. Therefore, the scale
is not identical with the ISCED scale.
Appendix 2
The question was posed as follows: “For each of these areas of technology development, do you
think it will have a positive, a negative or no effect on our way of life in the next 20 years?: Solar
energy, genetic engineering, nuclear energy, synthetic biology, information technology, nanotechnol-
ogy, stem cell research.”
Artificial Life Volume 22, Number 1
133
l
D
o
w
n
o
a
d
e
d
f
r
o
m
h
t
t
p
:
/
/
d
i
r
e
c
t
.
m
i
t
.
e
d
u
a
r
t
l
/
/
l
a
r
t
i
c
e
–
p
d
f
/
/
/
/
2
2
1
1
1
9
1
6
6
5
2
4
9
a
r
t
l
/
_
a
_
0
0
1
8
1
p
d
.
f
b
y
g
u
e
s
t
t
o
n
0
7
S
e
p
e
m
b
e
r
2
0
2
3
Download pdf