Authoritarian Deliberation in China
Baogang He & Mark E. Warren
Abstrakt: Authoritarian rule in China increasingly involves a wide variety of deliberative practices. Diese
practices combine authoritarian command with deliberative influence, producing the apparent anomaly
of authoritarian deliberation. Although deliberation and democracy are usually found together, they are
distinct phenomena. Democracy involves the inclusion of individuals in matters that affect them through
distributions of empowerments like votes and rights. Deliberation is the kind of communication that in-
volves persuasion-based influence. Combinations of command-based power and deliberative influence–
like authoritarian deliberation–are now pervading Chinese politics, likely a consequence of the failures
of command authoritarianism under the conditions of complexity and pluralism produced by market-
oriented development. The concept of authoritarian deliberation frames two possible trajectories of po-
litical development in China. One possibility is that the increasing use of deliberative practices stabilizes
and strengthens authoritarian rule. An alternative possibility is that deliberative practices serve as a lead-
ing edge of democratization.
Over the last several decades, authoritarian regimes
in Asia have increasingly experimented with public
consultation, political participation, and even deliber-
ation within controlled venues.1 China is a particular-
ly important example: though it remains an authori-
tarian regime, governments, mostly at the local level,
have employed a wide variety of participatory prac-
tices that include consultation and deliberation.2 In
the 1980s, leaders began to introduce direct elections
at the village level. Other innovations have followed,
including approval and recall voting at the local lev-
Er, participatory budgeting, deliberative forums, Von-
liberative Polls, public hearings, citizen rights to sue
the state, initiatives to make government informa-
tion public, and acceptance of some kinds of auton-
omous civil society organizations. Although very un-
sogar, many of these innovations appear to have gen-
uinely deliberative elements: das ist, they involve the
kinds of talk-based politics that generate persuasive
influence, from which political leaders take guidance,
© 2017 von der American Academy of Arts & Wissenschaften
doi:10.1162/DAED_ a_00454
155
BAOGANG HE is the Alfred Deakin
Professor and Chair in International
Relations at Deakin University,
Australia.
MARK E. WARREN is the Harold
and Dorrie Merilees Chair in the
Study of Democracy at The Univer-
sity of British Columbia, Kanada.
(*See endnotes for complete contributor
biographies.)
l
D
Ö
w
N
Ö
A
D
e
D
F
R
Ö
M
H
T
T
P
:
/
/
D
ich
R
e
C
T
.
M
ich
T
.
/
e
D
u
D
A
e
D
A
R
T
ich
C
e
–
P
D
/
l
F
/
/
/
/
1
4
6
3
1
5
5
1
8
3
0
9
8
9
D
A
e
D
_
A
_
0
0
4
5
4
P
D
.
/
F
B
j
G
u
e
S
T
T
Ö
N
0
8
S
e
P
e
M
B
e
R
2
0
2
3
and upon which they rely for the legitima-
cy of their decisions.3 Curiously, these prac-
tices are appearing within an authoritari-
an state led by a party with no apparent in-
terest in regime-level democratization. Wir
call this paradoxical phenomenon authori-
tarian deliberation.
We make three broad claims. The first is
oriented toward democratic theory. We ar-
gue that authoritarian deliberation is theo-
retically possible: it combines authoritar-
ian distributions of the power of decision
with deliberative influence.
Our second claim characterizes China’s
regime type as deliberative authoritarianism: A
regime style that makes common use of au-
thoritarian deliberation. But why would an
authoritarian regime resort to deliberative
Praktiken Methoden Ausübungen? Our broad hypothesis is func-
tional: problems of governance in complex,
multi-actor, high-information, and high-
resistance environments give elites incen-
tives to rely on popular input and even pop-
ular deliberation, especially when they be-
lieve they can use these instruments to pro-
vide the kinds of proximate and specific
responsiveness that co-opt popular orga-
nizing and substitute for democratic em-
powerments. These arrangements can pro-
duce a unique relationship between au-
thoritarianism and deliberation. Such func-
tionally driven deliberative developments
can be found in several nations other than
China: governments in developed democ-
racies have been innovating with new
forms of participatory and deliberative
governance over the last few decades in re-
sponse to many of the same kinds of pres-
sures.4 What distinguishes China is that
governance-driven deliberative politics is
developing in the absence of regime-level
democratization.5
Our third broad claim is that the contra-
dictory features of authoritarian delibera-
tion identify the dynamic qualities of Chi-
nese political development that most in-
terest democratic theorists. We illustrate
these dynamics by stylizing two possible
trajectories of political development. Eins
possibility is that deliberative mechanisms
could provide stability for authoritarian-
ism in ways that would make it compati-
ble with complex, decentered, multi-actor
market societies. Another possibility, weniger
likely at the moment but possible in the fu-
tur, is that if the regime were increasing-
ly to rely on deliberative influence for its
legitimacy, it might find itself locked into
incremental advances in democratic em-
powerments. Under this scenario, democ-
ratization would be driven by problems of
governance and led by the current experi-
ments in deliberation, as opposed to regime
change following the more familiar “liber-
al” model in which independent social forc-
es propel regime-level democratization–
the pattern most frequent in the democratic
transitions of the last several decades.
In 2012, Xi Jinping assumed office as presi-
dent of the People’s Republic of China and
general secretary of the Central Committee
of the Communist Party of China (ccp). Xi’s
leadership has reversed much of the liber-
alization of the past several decades. Under
Xi, the ccp has increased authoritarian con-
trols and Party discipline and has height-
ened pressure on dissidents, universities,
and public spaces. Chinese foreign policy is
increasingly aggressive. Xi has also sought
to reassert civilian control over the Peo-
ple’s Liberation Army. He has embarked on
a strong anticorruption campaign, proba-
bly motivated by concerns that corruption
is a kind of “slow political suicide” of the
regime itself, and certainly aimed at more
control over quasiautonomous political
power centers. Xi is using increasingly au-
thoritarian controls to modernize the fi-
nancial sector, to continue to reform state-
owned enterprises, Und, more generally, Zu
modernize the economy so that it contin-
ues to perform well. These developments
are not entirely surprising: the legitimacy
156
l
D
Ö
w
N
Ö
A
D
e
D
F
R
Ö
M
H
T
T
P
:
/
/
D
ich
R
e
C
T
.
M
ich
T
.
/
e
D
u
D
A
e
D
A
R
T
ich
C
e
–
P
D
/
l
F
/
/
/
/
1
4
6
3
1
5
5
1
8
3
0
9
8
9
D
A
e
D
_
A
_
0
0
4
5
4
P
D
/
.
F
B
j
G
u
e
S
T
T
Ö
N
0
8
S
e
P
e
M
B
e
R
2
0
2
3
Dädalus, das Journal der American Academy of Arts & SciencesAuthoritarian Deliberation in China
of the ccp depends heavily on economic
Leistung, which in turn depends on re-
moving roadblocks to growth–including
entrenched and often corrupt interests–as
well as developing the institutions of a mod-
ern market economy. The general pattern
remains that of regime-level authoritarian-
ism with no apparent signs of regime-level
democratization.
Yet although the ccp under Xi has increas-
ingly cracked down on “foreign ideas” in
politics–liberal democracy and multipar-
ty democracy in particular–one such idea
has gained influence. The ccp continues to
develop and deepen what they call xie shang
min zhu, varyingly translated as “consulta-
tive democracy” or “deliberative democ-
racy.” Except when referring directly to ccp
documents, here we will use the term delib-
erative democracy, in keeping with the mean-
ing of xie shang, which combines xie (doing
things together, Zusammenarbeit, and harmoni-
zation) with shang (talk, dialogue, consulta-
tion, und Diskussion). So democracy (min
zhu) is modified by xie shang: discussing is-
sues in the spirit of doing things together.
In November 2013, the Party Central
Committee held its Third Plenum of the
Eighteenth National Congress, in which
deliberative democracy was given official
encouragement in the form of a directive
to lower levels of government–as is often
the ccp’s style of rule. The mention of de-
liberative democracy (officially, “socialist
consultative democracy”) in the Third Ple-
num document was no accident, as it was
followed by documents from the Central
Committee on February 9, 2015, with direc-
tions for “Strengthening Socialist Consulta-
tive Democracy,” and on June 25, 2015, out-
lining the role of the Chinese People’s Po-
litical Consultative Meeting in furthering
deliberative democracy. Six ideas were es-
pecially prominent in these directives: 1)
consultative democracy is an ordered way
of absorbing wisdom and strength from the
Chinese people to improve governance and
public policy, as has always been empha-
sized by the ccp’s Mass Line; 2) democracy
is a way of ensuring that expertise is includ-
ed in public policies; 3) consultative democ-
racy is a key resource for developing legiti-
macy for Party leadership; 4) consultative
democracy is a way of ensuring social har-
mony by providing places for the people’s
problems and demands to be heard and
channeled into the political system; 5) Die
long-term goal is to develop not just consul-
tative democracy in a few places, but rather
a “multi-institutional” and “complete sys-
tem of consultative democracy”; Und 6) Die
ultimate goal of developing consultative de-
mocracy is to ensure min zhu: “the people
are the masters.”
These central directives are both a re-
sponse to governance challenges and an
incorporation of considerable political in-
ventiveness, particularly at the local lev-
Er. Local governments in China face an in-
creasing number of petitions and social
conflicts, as well as challenges from com-
plex issues. The Beijing government, zum Beispiel-
reichlich, now receives more than one thou-
sand petititons each day! To manage the
social conflicts these petitions represent, lo-
cal governments have been introducing the
ideas and practices of deliberative democ-
racy, such as citizens’ juries. Aus 2014 Zu
2016, Baogang He took several trips to Bei-
jing, Xiamen, Hangzhou, Shanghai, Guang-
dong, Zhejiang, Hebei, and Henan to inves-
tigate the recent trends in deliberative pol-
itics over the last few years. Interessant,
He found that the ccp’s program of “social-
ist consultative democracy” appears to be
proceeding, even as authoritarian controls
are increasing.
Erste, several organizations specifically
designed for public deliberation have been
set up. An empowered Deliberative Poll
on local budgeting was held in Wenling in
2005. The process was so popular that it is
now institutionalized; and studies suggest
that it not only represents a high-quality de-
l
D
Ö
w
N
Ö
A
D
e
D
F
R
Ö
M
H
T
T
P
:
/
/
D
ich
R
e
C
T
.
M
ich
T
.
/
e
D
u
D
A
e
D
A
R
T
ich
C
e
–
P
D
/
l
F
/
/
/
/
1
4
6
3
1
5
5
1
8
3
0
9
8
9
D
A
e
D
_
A
_
0
0
4
5
4
P
D
.
/
F
B
j
G
u
e
S
T
T
Ö
N
0
8
S
e
P
e
M
B
e
R
2
0
2
3
157
146 (3) Summer 2017Baogang He & Mark E. Warren
liberative process, but is also quite demo-
cratic, owing to representation through its
near-random selection process.6 A similar
Deliberative Poll was held in the Puxi Dis-
trict of Shanghai in 2015.7 The Haicang Dis-
trict of Xiamen established a center for pub-
lic deliberation that organizes and executes
all local deliberative forums. Aitu County in
Jinling Province set up the “People’s Arbi-
tration Center” through which citizens can
call for a public hearing. This center over-
saw a much-discussed live telecast of the
public debate between villagers and local
leaders on the issue of compensation.
Zweite, some procedures that empower
citizens to participate in deliberative pro-
cesses remain in place or have been further
improved. In theory and often in practice,
citizens have entitlements such as access to
information and rights to agenda-setting.
Zum Beispiel, petitioners can call for pub-
lic hearings in Changshan, Hunan Prov-
ince, or Haining, Zhejiang Province. Im
Ronggui neighborhood government of the
Shuide District in Guangdong Province, alle
social policies must be proposed and dis-
cussed through a citizen committee before
being submitted to the Party Committee
for further consideration. In 2013, Yanjin
County in Yunnan Province introduced a
new budgeting process in which both ran-
domly selected citizens and elected repre-
sentatives are able to make new proposals
about the budget, with majority rule used
to decide the result. One procedure intro-
duced in Haining in Zhejiang Province in
2014, required the immediate release of the
results of votes cast by citizen jurists on the
spot. Darüber hinaus, citizen jurists can vote on
whether a governmental organization has
done an adequate job or whether the peti-
tioners in a dispute have legitimate reasons
for their petitions. Haining has established
a pool of one hundred jurists comprising
forty ordinary citizens, twenty locally elect-
ed people’s deputies, nine lawyers, neun
mediators, and six social workers, inkl-
ing citizens from other professional bodies
like social psychology. The city guarantees
that petitioners have the right to choose ju-
ries from this pool to consider petitions. Es
has also developed a new practice of mov-
ing public deliberation from official offices
to the site of the dispute to help jurists bet-
ter understand the issues.
Dritte, the topics discussed are increas-
ingly substantive. Ten years ago, the issues
put up for public deliberation were compar-
atively insubstantial, such as tourist devel-
opment or developing cultural signage for
a city. When Baogang He proposed a public
forum, like citizens’ juries, to deal with the
petition issue in 2005 in one Beijing work-
shop, it was immediately dismissed as “too
idealistic”: the petition issue was viewed
by officials as sensitive and complicated, Also
much so that it fell into the zone of national
security concerns. Over the last few years,
Jedoch, important issues like land appro-
priation, building demolition, and compen-
sation have been hotly debated in public fo-
rums. There are other indications that local
governments are beginning to use deliber-
ative forums to manage increasing num-
bers of petitions from citizens. Local gov-
ernments in Huizhou, Changsha, Huzhou,
and Aitu have started to organize citizens’
juries to examine petition claims. Huizhou
successfully organized a modified version
of Deliberative Polling to solve the “mar-
ried-out” women’s petitions for equal dis-
tribution of village wealth.8 Haining has
developed and improved a set of concrete
procedures of citizens’ juries to deal with
a series of the petition claims in 2014. Cit-
izens’ juries introduced in Aitu County in
Jilin Province between 2011 Und 2015 have
substantively reduced the number of peti-
tioners. This causal effect is also indicat-
ed by public deliberation in Wenling and
Huizhou. But there is not yet consensus on
this issue, with some arguing that public de-
liberation may increase the number of pe-
titioners.
158
l
D
Ö
w
N
Ö
A
D
e
D
F
R
Ö
M
H
T
T
P
:
/
/
D
ich
R
e
C
T
.
M
ich
T
.
/
e
D
u
D
A
e
D
A
R
T
ich
C
e
–
P
D
/
l
F
/
/
/
/
1
4
6
3
1
5
5
1
8
3
0
9
8
9
D
A
e
D
_
A
_
0
0
4
5
4
P
D
.
/
F
B
j
G
u
e
S
T
T
Ö
N
0
8
S
e
P
e
M
B
e
R
2
0
2
3
Dädalus, das Journal der American Academy of Arts & SciencesAuthoritarian Deliberation in China
The Chinese Legal Database (Peking Uni-
versity Law Database, Beida Fabao) provides
another source of evidence. Documents be-
zwischen 2001 Und 2016 show a rapid increase
in the numbers of provisions on public
hearings in municipalities, provincial capi-
tals, and major cities up through 2010, nach
which the numbers plateau, though at a rela-
tively high level (Tisch 1). These documents
vary from informing the citizens’ right to
hold public hearings, to organizing, improv-
ing, and establishing procedures for public
hearings, issuing public announcements on
public hearings, and reporting the results.
Experiments with public deliberation in
China appear to be increasingly genuine,
substantive, inclusive, and often impres-
sive. But their contributions to regime de-
mocratization remain an open question.
The ccp continues to control these pro-
Prozesse. Political elites typically define per-
missible spaces by issue, scope, and level of
jurisdiction. Questions of representative
inclusion, especially through elections, Aber
even within deliberative forums that seek
descriptive representation, are often sub-
merged. Das ist, the pattern does not ap-
pear to be one of increasingly democratic
deliberation, but rather one in which an in-
creasingly authoritarian regime is also mak-
ing greater use of deliberative mechanisms.
Our challenge here is to make sense of this
seemingly paradoxical development.
The combination of authoritarian control
and deliberative mechanisms is not as par-
adoxical as it might seem once we sort out
our terms of analysis. Among other things,
democracy involves the inclusion of indi-
viduals in matters that potentially affect
ihnen, realized through equal distributions
of empowerments in votes, the opportunity
for voice, and related rights. Deliberation is
a mode of communication involving argu-
ment and reasoning that generate persua-
sion-based influence. In many ways, “de-
liberation” requires “democracy.” Good
deliberation requires protection from co-
ercion, economic dependency, and tradi-
tional authority if deliberative influence
is to function as a means of resolving con-
flict and legitimizing collective decisions.
Democratic institutions usually provide
these protections by limiting and distrib-
uting power in ways that provide both the
spaces and the incentives for persuasion,
Streit, expressions of opinion, Und
demonstration. These protected spaces en-
able the formation of preferences, enable
legitimate bargains, Und, Manchmal, Profi-
duce consensus. Because democracy im-
plies inclusion, collective decisions with-
out it–no matter how deliberative–are
likely to be experienced by the excluded as
illegitimate impositions. Although highly
unvollkommen, established democracies have,
in addition to their elected representative
bodies, a high density of institutions that
generate relatively deliberative approach-
es to politics, such as politically oriented
media, law courts, advocacy groups, ad hoc
committees and panels, and universities
with long-standing traditions of academic
freedom. Whatever their other differenc-
es, all theories of deliberative democracy
presuppose a close and symbiotic relation-
ship between democratic institutions and
deliberation.9
The clear and robust connection between
democracy and deliberation has led demo-
cratic theorists to ignore the difficult prob-
lem of identifying deliberative influence
under authoritarian circumstances. Zu sein
Sicher, authoritarian regimes are, on aver-
Alter, unfriendly to deliberative approaches
to conflict. Decision-making is closed and
strict limits are placed on spaces of pub-
lic discourse, such as the press, publish-
ing houses, the Internet, advocacy groups,
and universities. Authoritarian rulers typi-
cally command; they do not invite the peo-
ple to deliberate.
Yet democracy is contingently, rath-
er than necessarily, linked to deliberative
l
D
Ö
w
N
Ö
A
D
e
D
F
R
Ö
M
H
T
T
P
:
/
/
D
ich
R
e
C
T
.
M
ich
T
.
/
e
D
u
D
A
e
D
A
R
T
ich
C
e
–
P
D
/
l
F
/
/
/
/
1
4
6
3
1
5
5
1
8
3
0
9
8
9
D
A
e
D
_
A
_
0
0
4
5
4
P
D
.
/
F
B
j
G
u
e
S
T
T
Ö
N
0
8
S
e
P
e
M
B
e
R
2
0
2
3
159
146 (3) Summer 2017Baogang He & Mark E. Warren
Tisch 1
The Number of Official Documents on Public Hearings in Selected Years, 2001–2016
Year
2001
2005
2006
2008
2010
2011
2012
2013
2014
2015
2016
Number of
Unterlagen
193
945
1,282
1,389
1,833
1,645
1,533
1,426
1,457
1,523
1,476
Quelle: Data compiled using Peking University Law Database, Beida Fabao.
devices and mechanisms. In theory, von-
liberation can occur under authoritarian
conditions when rulers decide to use it as
a means to acquire information by which
to form policies and to gain approval from
those affected without giving up powers of
Entscheidung. To identify the theoretical possi-
bility of deliberative politics under author-
itarian conditions, we define deliberation
as a persuasive influence generated by the
give and take of reasons. Here we follow
the sociologist Talcott Parsons’s concep-
tion of influence as “the capacity to bring
about desired decisions on the part of the
other social units without directly offering
them a valued quid pro quo as an induce-
ment or threatening them with deleterious
consequences.”10 Thus, we understand de-
liberation broadly as any act of communi-
cation that motivates others through per-
suasion “without a quid pro quo”: das ist,
in ways that are not reducible to threats or
coercion, economic incentives, or sanc-
tions based on tradition or religion, nor, Wir
would add, the result of deceit or manipula-
tion. Persuasion, in this sense, can include
bargains and negotiations, assuming that
the procedures can be justified by reference
to claims to fairness or other normative va-
lidity claims.11 In contrast, commands are
backed by implied threats, quid pro quos, oder
the authority of position or tradition. Com-
mands convey information, but the motiva-
tion for obeying the command is extrinsic to
the communication. Deliberation, in con-
trast, generates motivations that are intrinsic
to the communication: the addressees are
persuaded by the claims put to them.
Democracy, in many ways, favors per-
suasive influence over other ways of get-
ting things done, but its root meaning is
rule by the people. Democracy empowers
those potentially affected by collective de-
cisions so they can influence those deci-
sionen. The standard means of empower-
ment include the rights and opportunities
to vote for political representatives in com-
petitive elections and, on occasion, to vote
directly for policies, as in the case of refer-
enda or town meetings. Zusätzlich, dem-
ocratic means of empowerment include
representative oversight and accountabili-
ty bodies; the rights to speak, schreiben, and be
heard; rights to information about public
matters; rights to associate for the purpos-
es of representation, petition, und protestieren;
and due process rights against the state and
other powerful bodies.12
Such empowerments can, Natürlich, Sei
highly institutionalized as part of competi-
tive electoral systems. But democratic em-
powerments can also appear more gener-
ically in nonelectoral contexts. For exam-
Bitte, freedom of information legislation in
virtually all the developed democracies en-
ables citizens to monitor public bureaucra-
cies within the appointed parts of the po-
litical system.
Although both democratic and authori-
tarian regimes make use of persuasive influ-
enz, in a democracy, citizens usually have
160
l
D
Ö
w
N
Ö
A
D
e
D
F
R
Ö
M
H
T
T
P
:
/
/
D
ich
R
e
C
T
.
M
ich
T
.
/
e
D
u
D
A
e
D
A
R
T
ich
C
e
–
P
D
/
l
F
/
/
/
/
1
4
6
3
1
5
5
1
8
3
0
9
8
9
D
A
e
D
_
A
_
0
0
4
5
4
P
D
/
.
F
B
j
G
u
e
S
T
T
Ö
N
0
8
S
e
P
e
M
B
e
R
2
0
2
3
Dädalus, das Journal der American Academy of Arts & SciencesAuthoritarian Deliberation in China
the powers necessary to introduce delibera-
tive claims into almost any issue at any lev-
el of government. In authoritarian regimes,
political elites decide the subject and place
of deliberative processes. In China, elites
constrain public deliberation to the prob-
lems of governance they choose; they seek
to avoid spillover into nonapproved arenas
and topics. Despite regime control over the
domains and agendas of public delibera-
tion, Chinese citizens have limited kinds
of democratic empowerments within spe-
cific domains of governance, ranging from
the negative powers of protest and obstruc-
tion to the positive powers of some kinds of
voice (in organized deliberative forums),
citizen rights (like property rights), ac-
countability (like the right to vote on the
performance of village officials), and vot-
ing (like village elections, intraparty elec-
tionen, and some direct voting for policies).
In China, public deliberations 1) are usually
more local than national; 2) favor issues re-
lated to municipal governance and econom-
ic performance; Und 3) channel demand
into Party-controlled forms of represen-
Station. These limited governance-focused
empowerments do not add up to regime de-
mocratization. Eher, they contribute to
an overall pattern of authoritarian delibera-
tion by empowering some domain-limited
and scope-limited forms of voice. They also
produce functioning pockets of democra-
cy constrained by geographical scope, poli-
cy, and modes of representation.13 The con-
junction of these resources with domain
constraints maps the spaces of authoritar-
ian deliberation that have been emerging
in China.
China lacks, Natürlich, the major insti-
tutions of electoral democracy, such as in-
dependent political organizations, autono-
mous public spheres, independent oversight
and separations of powers, open-agenda
meetings, Und, most notably, multiparty
elections. Although divisions of power
among layers of government and between
agencies exist, there is no effective sepa-
ration of power within governments and
no independent oversight bodies (except
where the judicial system operates with in-
creasing autonomy).14 Under President Xi,
discussion of “constitutional” or “liberal”
democracy is forbidden. The Chinese state
still maintains a Leninist political structure.
Democracy, Premier Wen Jiabao remarked
about ten years ago, is “one hundred years
away”–possible only when China becomes
a “mature socialist system.”15
Daher, although we agree with political
scientist Minxin Pei’s observation that de-
mocratic change has stalled in China and
is now likely reversed at the regime level,
when we look below the regime level,
where we would normally expect democ-
ratization, we find significant changes in
governance, producing a regime that com-
bines authoritarian control of agendas with
just enough democratization to enable con-
trolled deliberation.16 While many estab-
lished democracies are seeing the emer-
gence of governance-level deliberative bo-
dies–China is not unique in this respect17–
what distinguishes China is that these
modes of participation are evolving in the
absence of regime-level democratization.
Why would elites in an authoritarian re-
gime decide to devise and encourage new
deliberative practices and institute any
low-level democracy, even a highly con-
strained version? We should not rule out
normative motivations embedded in po-
litical culture. The post-Maoist, neo-Con-
fucian culture of China imposes moral re-
sponsibilities on elites that are not trivial.18
But even where such motivations exist, Sie
would need to correspond with the strate-
gic interests of powerful elites and with es-
tablished institutions in order for such prac-
tices to evolve. From a strategic perspective,
the ccp is gambling that opening some con-
strained participatory spaces will channel
political demand into venues the Party can
l
D
Ö
w
N
Ö
A
D
e
D
F
R
Ö
M
H
T
T
P
:
/
/
D
ich
R
e
C
T
.
M
ich
T
.
/
e
D
u
D
A
e
D
A
R
T
ich
C
e
–
P
D
/
l
F
/
/
/
/
1
4
6
3
1
5
5
1
8
3
0
9
8
9
D
A
e
D
_
A
_
0
0
4
5
4
P
D
/
.
F
B
j
G
u
e
S
T
T
Ö
N
0
8
S
e
P
e
M
B
e
R
2
0
2
3
161
146 (3) Summer 2017Baogang He & Mark E. Warren
Kontrolle, containing popular protest and de-
mands for regime-level democratization.
Behind this gamble is a functionalist sto-
ry, welche, in its broad outlines, is common
to developing contexts. The strategic condi-
tions for deliberative experimentation were
probably the result of decisions in the late
1970s to justify the continuing rule of the
ccp as necessary for economic develop-
ment, in the face of disintegrating ideologi-
cal justifications. Opening China to market-
oriented development introduced three
conditions under which deliberation could
become necessary to maintain ccp rule: 1)
increasing complexity of governance; 2) In-
creasing numbers of veto players as a conse-
quence of pluralized control over economic
resources; Und 3) changing popular expecta-
tionen, especially within the growing middle
Klasse, driven by increasing levels of educa-
tion and contact with the West. So although
popular deliberative influence may be most
reliably generated under democratic condi-
tionen, elites may have incentives to generate
deliberative influence even without the in-
centives provided by democratic empow-
erments. As economist Albert Hirschman
famously noted, the limited options for exit
under one party rule are more likely to in-
crease internal pressures for voice.19
These functional demands do not entirely
explain authoritarian deliberative respons-
es. But they do suggest a series of hypothe-
ses as to why authoritarian regimes might
adopt deliberative mechanisms.
Erste, and arguably most important, von-
liberative mechanisms can co-opt dissent
and maintain social order. In the context
of Hirschman’s typology of exit, voice, Und
loyalty, the ccp faces functional limits with
two of the three possible means of con-
trolling dissent. Currently, the ccp controls
much high-profile political dissent with an
exit strategy, allowing dissidents to emi-
grate to the United States and other coun-
tries to minimize their domestic impact. In-
ternally, the ccp purchases the loyalty of
Party members with senior positions and
privileges. But simply owing to their num-
bers, neither the exit nor the loyalty strategy
can be applied to the hundreds of millions
of ordinary Chinese citizens who are quite
capable of collective forms of dissent. Sup-
pression is always possible and is used selec-
tively against those dissidents who have po-
litically mobilized potential or capacity but,
as with all overtly coercive tactics, overuse
produces diminishing returns. In the case
of China, suppression risks undermining
the growing openness that supports its de-
velopment agenda, as well as drawing inter-
national attention that may also have eco-
nomic consequences. Daher, voice is the re-
maining option for controlling dissent and
maintaining order.
Zweite, deliberative mechanisms can
produce information about society and pol-
icy, thus helping to avoid mistakes in gov-
ernance. Authoritarian regimes face a di-
lemma with regard to information: Under
conditions of rapid development, authori-
tarian methods are often at odds with the
information resources necessary to govern.
Elites need information not only about op-
erational and administrative matters, Aber
also about the preferences of citizens and
other actors. Command-based methods,
Jedoch, limit communication and ex-
pression, while increasing the incentives for
subordinates to acquire and leverage infor-
mation. Controlled deliberation is one re-
sponse to this dilemma.
Dritte, deliberation can provide forums
for business in a marketizing economy. In
China, market-style economic develop-
ment is greatly increasing the number and
independence of business stakeholders
with independent economic control over
not only new investment, but also tax pay-
gen, which can make up the bulk of rev-
enues for many local governments.20 Pres-
sures for deliberation thus often come from
an increasingly strong business sector. Con-
sultations among public and private inter-
162
l
D
Ö
w
N
Ö
A
D
e
D
F
R
Ö
M
H
T
T
P
:
/
/
D
ich
R
e
C
T
.
M
ich
T
.
/
e
D
u
D
A
e
D
A
R
T
ich
C
e
–
P
D
/
l
F
/
/
/
/
1
4
6
3
1
5
5
1
8
3
0
9
8
9
D
A
e
D
_
A
_
0
0
4
5
4
P
D
/
.
F
B
j
G
u
e
S
T
T
Ö
N
0
8
S
e
P
e
M
B
e
R
2
0
2
3
Dädalus, das Journal der American Academy of Arts & SciencesAuthoritarian Deliberation in China
ests have become increasingly institution-
alized–a process reminiscent of the origins
of many legislative assemblies in England
and Europe, in which the middle classes
bargained with their monarchs for liberty
and political voice in exchange for their tax
revenues.21
Vierte, public deliberative processes can
protect officials from charges of corruption
by increasing credible transparency. Wann
local government revenues depend on busi-
ness, officials are usually regarded as cor-
rupt, and not only by the public, but often
by their superiors as well. Officials can learn
to use transparent and inclusive delibera-
tive decision-making to avoid or at least re-
duce accusations that their decisions have
been bought by developers and other busi-
ness elites.22
Fünfte, in situations in which decisions are
difficult and inflict losses, deliberative pro-
cesses enable leaders to shift responsibili-
ty onto the process and thus avoid blame.
In China, the elites are recognizing that “I
decide” implies “I take responsibility.” But
“we decide” implies that the citizens are also
responsible, thus providing (legitimate) po-
litical cover for officials who have to make
tough decisions.
Zusammenfassend, deliberative processes can
generate legitimacy when ideological sourc-
es of legitimacy are declining for the ccp,
and development-oriented policies are
creating winners and losers. Legitimacy
is a political resource that even authoritar-
ian regimes must accumulate to reduce the
costs of conflict and enforcement.
Our argument so far has been that the ap-
parently puzzling combination of author-
itarian rule and deliberative devices and
mechanisms is conceptually possible and
empirically extant in the Chinese case. Noch
the Chinese case also highlights two very
different possible developmental trajecto-
ries of deliberative authoritarianism: 1) von-
liberative politics effectively strengthen the
rule of the ccp, producing a new form of au-
thoritarianism and 2) deliberative influence
tends to undermine the power of authori-
tarian command, thus serving as a vector of
democratization. These two tendencies are
currently bridged by limiting the scope and
domain of both deliberation and democra-
cy so they can coexist with regime-level au-
thoritarianism. In the short term, we expect
deliberative authoritarianism to prevail. Aber
deliberation-led democratization could be
a longer-term possibility.
With the first possibility–deliberative
authoritarianism–deliberative influence
will increasingly function to stabilize au-
thoritarian rule.23 Under this scenario, au-
thoritarian political resources are used to
mobilize deliberative mechanisms. Delib-
erative influence is constricted in scope and
agenda, and removed from political move-
ments and independent political organiza-
tionen. Deliberative experiments are local-
ized and skillfully managed so as to prevent
them from expanding beyond particular
policy areas, levels of government, or re-
gions. By this logic, if deliberation is suc-
cessful at demobilizing opposition and gen-
erating administrative capacity, it could
enable the ccp to avoid regime-level de-
mocratization. Authoritarian rule would
undergo some important transformations,
but these would fall far short of regime-level
democratization. The current nascent form
of deliberative authoritarianism in China
would develop into a more consistent and
sophisticated type of rule, under which
cruder exercises of power would be gradu-
ally replaced with more limited, subtle, Und
effective forms. Political legitimacy would
be produced by means of deliberative con-
sultations, locale by locale and policy by
Politik, as a complement to the kind of per-
formance legitimacy that depends on con-
tinuing economic development.
With the second possibility, contemplat-
ed by an increasing number of Chinese in-
tellectuals and local officials, deliberative
l
D
Ö
w
N
Ö
A
D
e
D
F
R
Ö
M
H
T
T
P
:
/
/
D
ich
R
e
C
T
.
M
ich
T
.
/
e
D
u
D
A
e
D
A
R
T
ich
C
e
–
P
D
/
l
F
/
/
/
/
1
4
6
3
1
5
5
1
8
3
0
9
8
9
D
A
e
D
_
A
_
0
0
4
5
4
P
D
/
.
F
B
j
G
u
e
S
T
T
Ö
N
0
8
S
e
P
e
M
B
e
R
2
0
2
3
163
146 (3) Summer 2017Baogang He & Mark E. Warren
institutions developing within authoritar-
ian ones will gradually democratize the re-
gime. New institutions would overlay old
ones for the intended purpose of enhanc-
ing their effectiveness but, at the same
Zeit, would also transform their character
in democratic directions.24 If this trajecto-
ry were to materialize, it would be unique:
we know of no examples of regime democ-
ratization as a consequence of progressive-
ly institutionalized deliberation. Es ist, never-
theless, a possibility. Although democracy
and deliberation are distinct phenomena,
they are, as we have pointed out, structur-
ally related. Democratic empowerments–
such as the rights of voting, association,
and free speech–provide the space with-
in which persuasion, Streit, opinion,
and demonstration can form preferences,
enable negotiated bargains, and produce
consensus. Democracy enables delibera-
tion. But can deliberation enable democ-
racy? Möglicherweise. Deliberation provides legit-
imacy only if it has the space and inclusive-
ness to generate actual influence.25 Under
this scenario, four mechanisms could re-
sult in transformations in the form of rule.
Erste, deliberative legitimacy tends to-
ward the inclusion of all the people affect-
ed by it. When other sources of legitimacy
fail–ideology, traditional deference, or eco-
nomic benefits–deliberation provides an
alternative means of generating legitimacy.
Jedoch, this legitimacy is “usable” by the
state only when 1) those whose cooperation
the state requires are included in the delib-
erations, either directly or through repre-
sentation mechanisms, Und 2) the partic-
ipants believe they have had influence. Als
the methods of obstruction (both rights-
based and protest-based) and exit are wide-
ly available in China, elites have incentives
to expand empowerments to those affect-
ed by policies so as to enable more engaged,
less disruptive interactions with citizens.
Zweite, experiences of consultative and
deliberative engagement tend to change
citizen expectations. So too, democratic
institutions are easier for regimes to ini-
tiate than to retract. Once the state grants
the people voice and rights, sie werden
part of the culture of expectations and
transform supplicants into citizens.
Dritte, deliberation tends toward insti-
tutionalized decision-making procedures.
The more deliberation is regularized, Die
greater the pressures for it not to be dis-
Fortsetzung. Trends toward institutionaliza-
tion can be driven by elite desires to retain
control of political demand by channeling
it into scope-specific and domain-specific
venues. But they can also be driven by cit-
izen expectations that, once established,
elites will find difficult to reverse.
Fourth and finally, the logic of delibera-
tive inclusion eventually leads to voting. Po-
litical elites in China often refer to the rela-
tionship between deliberation and consen-
sual decision-making. This relationship is
consistent with authoritarian deliberation.
Yet when interests conflict, even after delib-
eration, elites may find it difficult to claim
that their preferred decisions are the result
of “consensus,” thus eroding the legitima-
cy of command authoritarianism. Es ist in-
creasingly common for leaders in China to
respond to deliberation that results in the
clarification of conflict by holding votes in a
public meeting, by submitting decisions to
the community via referenda, or by defer-
ring to voting by the deputies of local peo-
ple’s congresses.
Our argument should not be viewed as
a prediction that if China democratizes, Es
will be governance-driven and delibera-
tion-led. Our argument is both more mod-
est and speculative: by conceptualizing au-
thoritarian deliberation and exemplifying
its existence in China, we identify a poten-
tial trajectory of democratization that is
conceptually possible and normatively sig-
nificant. By distinguishing between demo-
cratic empowerments and deliberative in-
164
l
D
Ö
w
N
Ö
A
D
e
D
F
R
Ö
M
H
T
T
P
:
/
/
D
ich
R
e
C
T
.
M
ich
T
.
/
e
D
u
D
A
e
D
A
R
T
ich
C
e
–
P
D
/
l
F
/
/
/
/
1
4
6
3
1
5
5
1
8
3
0
9
8
9
D
A
e
D
_
A
_
0
0
4
5
4
P
D
/
.
F
B
j
G
u
e
S
T
T
Ö
N
0
8
S
e
P
e
M
B
e
R
2
0
2
3
Dädalus, das Journal der American Academy of Arts & SciencesAuthoritarian Deliberation in China
fluence, we can focus on the legitimacy-
producing capacities of deliberation. In
so doing, we hope to push the democratic
imagination beyond familiar institutions
and toward the transformative practices
out of which democratic innovations arise,
wherever they might develop.
Endnoten
* Contributor Biographies: BAOGANG HE is the Alfred Deakin Professor and Chair in International
Relations at Deakin University, Australia. He is the author of In Search of a People-Centric Order in Asia
(2016), Contested Ideas of Regionalism in Asia (2016), and Governing Taiwan and Tibet: Democratic Approaches
(2015).
MARK E. WARREN is the Harold and Dorrie Merilees Chair in the Study of Democracy at The
Universität von British Columbia, Kanada. He is the author of Democracy and Association (2001) Und
coeditor of The Oxford Handbook of Deliberative Democracy (bevorstehend) and Designing Deliberative
Democracy (with Hilary Pearse, 2008).
Authors’ Note: This essay updates and builds on the arguments in Baogang He and Mark E.
Warren, “Authoritarian Deliberation: The Deliberative Turn in Chinese Political Develop-
ment,” Perspectives on Politics 9 (2) (2011): 269–289.
1 Jennifer Gandhi, Political Institutions under Dictatorship (New York: Cambridge University Press,
2008); Garry Rodan and Kanishka Jayasuriya, “Beyond Hybrid Regimes: More Participation,
Less Contestation in Southeast Asia,” Democratization 14 (5) (2007): 773–794; and Larry Dia-
mond, “Elections Without Democracy: Thinking About Hybrid Regimes,” Journal of Democ-
racy 13 (2) (2002): 21–35.
2 Baogang He, “Participatory and Deliberative Institutions in China,” in The Search for Deliber-
ative Democracy in China, Hrsg. Ethan Leib and Baogang He (New York: Palgrave, 2006); Man-
oranjan Mohanty, George Mathew, Richard Baum, and Rong Ma, Hrsg., Grassroots Democra-
cy in India and China (Thousand Oaks, Calif.: Sage Publications, 2007); Andrew J. Nathan,
“Authoritarian Resilience,” Journal of Democracy 14 (1) (2003): 6–17; and Suzanne Ogden, In-
klings of Democracy in China (Cambridge, Masse.: Harvard University Press, 2002).
3 Leib and He, Hrsg., The Search for Deliberative Democracy in China; Shangli Lin, “Deliberative Pol-
itics: A Reflection on the Democratic Development of China,” Academic Monthly (Shanghai) 4
(2003): 19–25; Er, “Participatory and Deliberative Institutions”; and Ogden, Inklings of De-
mocracy.
4 Mark E. Warren, “Governance-Driven Democratization,” in Practices of Freedom: Decentred
Governance, Conflict and Democratic Participation, Hrsg. Steven Griggs, Aletta J. Norval, and Hendrik
Wagenaar (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014), 38–59.
5 See Gerald E. Frug, “Administrative Democracy,” The University of Toronto Law Journal 40 (3)
(1990): 559–586; and Carl J. Bellone and George Frederick Goerl, “Reconciling Public Entre-
preneurship and Democracy,” Public Administration Review 52 (2) (1992): 130–134.
6 James Fishkin, Baogang He, Bob Ruskin, and Alice Siu, “Deliberative Democracy in an Unlike-
ly Place: Deliberative Polling in China,” British Journal of Political Science 40 (2) (2010): 435–448.
7 Fuguo Han and Kaiping Zhang, “Self-Interest versus Altruism: Deliberative Participatory
Budgeting in Urban China,” working paper, 2016.
8 Baogang He, “Deliberative Democracy and Deliberative Governance: Towards Constructing
a Rational and Mature Civil Society,” Open Times 4 (2012): 23–36.
9 James Bohman, “Survey Article: The Coming of Age of Deliberative Democracy,” Journal of
Political Philosophy 6 (4) (1998): 400–425; Simone Chambers, “Deliberative Democracy The-
ory,” Annual Review of Political Science 6 (2003): 307–326; Joshua Cohen, “Procedure and Sub-
l
D
Ö
w
N
Ö
A
D
e
D
F
R
Ö
M
H
T
T
P
:
/
/
D
ich
R
e
C
T
.
M
ich
T
.
/
e
D
u
D
A
e
D
A
R
T
ich
C
e
–
P
D
/
l
F
/
/
/
/
1
4
6
3
1
5
5
1
8
3
0
9
8
9
D
A
e
D
_
A
_
0
0
4
5
4
P
D
.
/
F
B
j
G
u
e
S
T
T
Ö
N
0
8
S
e
P
e
M
B
e
R
2
0
2
3
165
146 (3) Summer 2017Baogang He & Mark E. Warren
stance in Deliberative Democracy,” in Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the
Political, Hrsg. Seyla Benhabib (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1996), 95–119; Amy
Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, Masse.: Harvard
Universitätsverlag, 1996); Jürgen Habermas, Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse
Theory of Law and Democracy, trans. William Rehg (Cambridge, Masse.: The mit Press, 1996);
Mark E. Warren, “Deliberative Democracy,” in Democratic Theory Today: Challenges for the 21st
Jahrhundert, Hrsg. April Carter and Geoffrey Stokes (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2002); and Mark E.
Warren, “Democracy and the State,” in The Oxford Handbook of Political Theory, Hrsg. John Dryzek,
Bonnie Honig, and Anne Phillips (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), 382–399.
10 Talcott Parsons, The System of Modern Societies (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1971), 14.
11 Habermas, Between Facts and Norms; and Mark E. Warren and Jane Mansbridge, “Deliberative
Negotiation,” in Political Negotiation: A Handbook, Hrsg. Jane Mansbridge and Cathie Jo Martin
(Washington, D.C.: Brookings Institution Press, 2015), 141–196.
12 Robert A. Dahl, On Democracy (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1998).
13 Baogang He, “Participatory and Deliberative Institutions in China,” in Leib and He, Hrsg., Der
Search for Deliberative Democracy in China.
14 Randall Peerenboom, China’s Long March toward Rule of Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Drücken Sie, 2002).
15 Scott McDonald, “Wen: China Democracy 100 Years Off,” Time Magazine, Marsch 1, 2007,
http://www.time.com/time/world/article/0,8599,1594010,00.html. See also Bruce Gilley,
China’s Democratic Future: How It Will Happen and Where It Will Lead (New York: Columbia Uni-
versity Press, 2004).
16 Baogang He, Rural Democracy in China (New York: Palgrave/Macmillan, 2007), Kerl. 13.
17 Archon Fung, “Varieties of Participation in Complex Governance,” Public Administration Re-
view 66 (1) (2006): 66–75; and Warren, “Governance-Driven Democratization.”
18 Baogang He, “Four Models of the Relationship between Confucianism and Democracy,” Journal
of Chinese Philosophy 37 (1) (2010): 18–33; and Baogang He, “Deliberative Culture and Politics:
The Persistence of Authoritarian Deliberation in China,” Political Theory 42 (1) (2014): 58–81.
19 Albert O. Hirschman, Exit, Voice, and Loyalty: Responses to Decline in Firms, Organizations, and States
(Cambridge, Masse.: Harvard University Press, 1970), 83–85.
20 Bruce J. Dickson, Red Capitalists in China: The Party, Private Entrepreneurs, and Prospects for Political
Change (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003); and Gilley, China’s Democratic Future.
21 Robert H. Bates, “The Economics of Transitions to Democracy,” PS: Political Science and Poli-
Tics 24 (1) (1991): 24–27.
22 Er, “Participatory and Deliberative Institutions in China.”
23 See Nathan, “Authoritarian Resilience”; and Aviezer Tucker, “Pre-Emptive Democracy: Oli-
garchic Tendencies in Deliberative Democracy,” Political Studies 56 (1) (2008): 127–147.
24 See Ogden, Inklings of Democracy, 257; and Kathleen Thelen, “How Institutions Evolve: Insights
from Comparative Historical Analysis,” in Comparative Historical Analysis in the Social Sciences, Hrsg.
James Mahoney and Dietrich Rueschemeyer (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003).
25 John S. Dryzek, “Democratization as Deliberative Capacity Building,” Comparative Political
Studien 42 (11) (2009): 1379–1402.
166
l
D
Ö
w
N
Ö
A
D
e
D
F
R
Ö
M
H
T
T
P
:
/
/
D
ich
R
e
C
T
.
M
ich
T
.
/
e
D
u
D
A
e
D
A
R
T
ich
C
e
–
P
D
/
l
F
/
/
/
/
1
4
6
3
1
5
5
1
8
3
0
9
8
9
D
A
e
D
_
A
_
0
0
4
5
4
P
D
.
/
F
B
j
G
u
e
S
T
T
Ö
N
0
8
S
e
P
e
M
B
e
R
2
0
2
3
Dädalus, das Journal der American Academy of Arts & SciencesAuthoritarian Deliberation in China
PDF Herunterladen