INFORME

INFORME

People’s Intuitions About Innateness

1
Iris Berent

, Melanie Platt

1

1
, and Gwendolyn M. Sandoboe

1Department of Psychology, Northeastern University

un acceso abierto

diario

Palabras clave: innateness, core knowledge, dualism, essentialism

ABSTRACTO

Few questions in science are as controversial as the origins of knowledge. Whether
conocimiento (p.ej., “objects are cohesive”) is partly innate has been debated for centuries.
Aquí, we ask whether our difficulties with innate knowledge could be grounded in human
cognition itself. In eight experiments, we compared reasoning about the innateness of traits
that capture knowledge (cognitive traits) with noncognitive (sensorimotor and emotive)
traits. Experiments 1–4 examined adult and infant traits; Experimento 5 presented detailed
descriptions of published infant experiments. Results showed that people viewed cognitive
traits as less likely to be innate in humans—the stronger the association with “thinking,” the
lower the rating for “innateness.” Experiments 6–8 explored human, bird, and alien traits
that were presented as innate. Participantes, sin embargo, still considered cognitive traits as less
likely to emerge spontaneously (es decir., be innate). These results show that people are
selectively biased in reasoning about the origins of knowledge.

INTRODUCCIÓN

The origin of knowledge is one of the most controversial questions in the history of ideas. En
stake is whether knowledge (p.ej., the notion of an “object”) is induced from experience, o
whether certain cognitive concepts and principles are innate in humans. These debates have
been raging since the times of the ancient Greeks, and they show no sign of abating in the
current scientific literature.

Why is innateness such a hard question? There is no doubt that the innateness challenge
is partly due to the complexity of the problem at hand—the intricacy of human cognition and
its mostly unknown instantiation in the brain. But perhaps the reasons for the stalemate lie
not only with the topic of inquiry but also with the human inquirer. Here we ask whether our
understanding of innateness could be constrained by systematic biases that shape how people
reason about innate knowledge.

The possibility that people are not impartial to innateness has not gone unnoticed.
Cosmides and Tooby (1994) have argued that people suffer from “instinct blindness,” and
Pinker (2002) has warned against the denial of human nature. But these assertions are based
on anecdotal evidence. The question thus remains whether people are indeed blind to
innateness—no previous study has examined this possibility. Además, no research has asked
whether our blindness to innateness is particularly acute when it comes to knowledge (con
the exception of Wang & Feigenson, 2019, published in this issue).

Citación: Berent, I., Platón, METRO., &
Sandoboe, GRAMO. METRO. (2019). People’s
Intuitions About Innateness. Open
Mente: Discoveries in Cognitive
Ciencia, 3, 101–114. https://doi.org/
10.1162/opmi_a_00029

DOI:
https://doi.org/10.1162/opmi_a_00029

Materiales suplementarios:
https://doi.org/10.1162/opmi_a_00029

Recibió: 26 Enero 2019
Aceptado: 21 Agosto 2019

Conflicto de intereses: Los autores
declare that they have no competing
interests.

Autor correspondiente:
Iris Berent
i.berent@northeastern.edu

Derechos de autor: © 2019
Instituto de Tecnología de Massachusetts
Publicado bajo Creative Commons
Atribución 4.0 Internacional
(CC POR 4.0) licencia

La prensa del MIT

yo

D
oh
w
norte
oh
a
d
mi
d

F
r
oh
metro
h

t
t

pag

:
/
/

d
i
r
mi
C
t
.

metro

i
t
.

/

mi
d
tu
oh
pag
metro

i
/

yo

a
r
t
i
C
mi

pag
d

F
/

d
oh

i
/

i

/

.

1
0
1
1
6
2
oh
pag
metro
_
a
_
0
0
0
2
9
1
9
2
8
7
9
6
oh
pag
metro

/

/

i

0
3

1
0
1
pag
d

.

F

b
y
gramo
tu
mi
s
t

t

oh
norte
0
7
S
mi
pag
mi
metro
b
mi
r
2
0
2
3

People’s Intuitions About Innateness

Berent et al.

Knowledge, aquí, refers to tacit concepts and principles. Examples of putative in-
nate knowledge include tacit principles of core physics (p.ej., “objects are cohesive”; Spelke &
Kinzler,
2007) and core psychology (p.ej., “agents’ actions are determined by their
mental states”; Baron-Cohen, Leslie, & Frith, 1985), as well as their constituent concepts
(object; agent). Our research asks whether people are reluctant to accept that knowledge
can be innate.

There are various reasons to believe that the notion of innate knowledge might present a
special challenge to intuitive human cognition, reasons we explore in the General Discussion.
Our present inquiry, sin embargo, does not seek to explain why people are biased against innate
conocimiento, and we certainly do not intend to determine whether knowledge is in fact innate.
En cambio, we strictly ask whether people are guilty as charged—are we systematically biased in
evaluating the origins of our knowledge?

Para tal fin, we examine reasoning about the origins of various types of cognitive traits
that capture knowledge and compare them to sensory, emotional, and motor traits. We refer
to these traits generically as cognitive, but our interest is strictly in innate knowledge (p.ej.,
“objects are cohesive”), as opposed to “knowhow” (p.ej., playing the violin) or “horizontal”
faculties (p.ej., atención, memory, and problem solving).

In this investigation, we define “innate” psychological traits as psychological primitives—
ones that are acquired in the normal course of development without relying on other psy-
chological processes, most notably, aprendiendo (samuel, 2004, 2007). To gauge laypeople’s
reasoning about innateness, we thus asked participants to reflect on the tendency of psycho-
logical traits to emerge spontaneously in all members of the species and their early onset in
desarrollo (a hallmark of many innate traits). We also asked people to explicitly indicate
whether or not cognitive traits are innate.

We conducted two sets of experiments. In one set, we presented people with various
traits—both cognitive and noncognitive—and asked them to reason about their innateness.
To determine whether reasoning about innateness is biased, we next presented people with
detailed vignettes, stating that all traits in question are innate. Of interest is whether people
are reluctant to view cognitive traits as innate despite evidence that is clearly indicative of
innateness.

REASONING ABOUT HUMAN COGNITIVE TRAITS

Experiments 1–2: Rating Human Traits

Experiments 1–2 each presented people with a list of human traits. Experimento 1 featured
adult traits that have been documented cross-culturally; Experimento 2 featured infant traits.
En cada caso, half of the traits were cognitive and half were noncognitive, either motor and
emotive, or motor and sensory (in Experiments 1–2, respectivamente). Por ejemplo, adult cognitive
traits included “forming sentences” and “having a concept of ‘person’”; infant cognitive traits
included “Expecting objects to move as connected wholes (p.ej., without disintegrating)."

To ensure that these traits are perceived as indicative of cognition, we asked one group
of participants to classify the traits into three bins (p.ej., “thinking,” “emotion,” or “action”). A
second group of participants evaluated the innateness of these traits, operationalized as their
propensity to emerge spontaneously, in a “desert island” situation.

We examined three questions. Primero, do people view these cognitive traits as ones that are
indicative of “thinking”? Segundo, do people believe that cognitive traits are less likely to emerge

MENTE ABIERTA: Descubrimientos en ciencia cognitiva

102

yo

D
oh
w
norte
oh
a
d
mi
d

F
r
oh
metro
h

t
t

pag

:
/
/

d
i
r
mi
C
t
.

metro

i
t
.

/

mi
d
tu
oh
pag
metro

i
/

yo

a
r
t
i
C
mi

pag
d

F
/

d
oh

i
/

i

.

/

1
0
1
1
6
2
oh
pag
metro
_
a
_
0
0
0
2
9
1
9
2
8
7
9
6
oh
pag
metro

/

/

i

0
3

1
0
1
pag
d

.

F

b
y
gramo
tu
mi
s
t

t

oh
norte
0
7
S
mi
pag
mi
metro
b
mi
r
2
0
2
3

People’s Intuitions About Innateness

Berent et al.

spontaneously (es decir., be innate)? And third, is the rating of a trait for innateness associated with
its classification as “thinking”?

Experimento 1: Rating Adult Human Traits

Métodos

Two groups of participants (norte = 20 cada) were each assigned to the trait classi-
Participantes
fication and innate rating tasks. In this and all subsequent experiments, participants were adult
English speakers, recruited through Amazon Mechanical Turk.

The materials consisted of a randomized list of 80 human traits—
Materials and Procedure
half were cognitive—and half were noncognitive traits, either emotive (20 traits) or motor
(20 traits).

The trait list was presented to two groups of participants. One group classified each trait
into one of three bins—“thinking,” “action,” or “emotion.” A second group rated the traits for
innateness. Específicamente, people indicated on a 1–7 scale (1 = very unlikely; 7 = very likely)
how likely it is that a person would exhibit this trait spontaneously, in a desert island situation,
even if they did not have the opportunity to learn it from others. For additional method details,
ver los materiales complementarios; Berent, Platón, & Sandoboe, 2019b, which include the stimulus
materials and instructions for this and all subsequent experiments in Appendices 1–2.

Resultados

To determine whether most classification responses were congruent with
Trait Classification
the intended category (p.ej., “thinking,” for cognitive traits), we first computed the congruence
scores for cognitive and noncognitive traits (noncognitive traits were averaged over the “motor”
and “emotive” subcategories). We then compared the proportion of “congruent” responses
against chance (.5) using a mixed-effects logistic regression model (with participants and items
as random effects). Results demonstrated that ratings of cognitive (m = 0.79, β0 = 2.14,
Z = 5.00, SE = 0.43, pag < .0001) and noncognitive (M = 0.90, β0 = 3.58, Z = 7.58, SE = 0.47, p < .0001) traits were congruent with the intended category. Innateness Rating We next examined the rating of these traits for innateness (see Figure 1A). People rated noncognitive traits significantly higher than the scale’s “neutral” midpoint, 4; M = 5.65, t1(19) = 7.91, p < .0001, d = 1.77; t2(39) = 13.37, p < .0001, d = 2.11. For cognitive traits, by contrast, this difference was not significant across participants, M = 4.44, t1(19) = 1.68, p < .11, d = 0.38; t2(39) = 4.58, p < .0001, d = 0.72. A matched sample t test further showed that cognitive traits were rated as less likely to emerge spontaneously compared to noncognitive traits, and these results were significant across participants, t1(19) = 7.61, p < .0001, d = 1.10, and items, t2(78) = 7.76, p < .0001, d = 1.73. Finally, we examined whether reasoning about the innate- The “thinking”–“innateness” link. ness of cognitive traits is linked to their association with “thinking” (see Figure 1B). To this end, we correlated the rated propensity of each of our 80 traits to emerge spontaneously (our gauge of “innateness”) with its classification as “thinking.” The correlation was highly significant and negative, r(78) = −.680, p < .0001—the stronger the association of a trait with “thinking,” the less likely it was to be seen as spontaneously emerging (i.e., innate). OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science 103 l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . / e d u o p m i / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / i . / 1 0 1 1 6 2 o p m _ a _ 0 0 0 2 9 1 9 2 8 7 9 6 o p m / / i - 0 3 - 1 0 1 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 People’s Intuitions About Innateness Berent et al. Figure 1. The presumed innateness of adult human traits (A) and its association with “thinking” response (B). In this and all subsequent experiments, the scale’s midpoint is indicated by a dashed line. Error bars are 95% confidence intervals for the difference between the means. Scatter symbols indicate individual traits. Experiment 2: Rating Infant Human Traits Method Participants and innateness-rating tasks. Two groups of participants (N = 20 each) were assigned to the trait-classification The materials consisted of a randomized list of 32 infant traits: Materials and Procedure 16 cognitive and 16 noncognitive (10 motor and 6 sensory traits). Participants in the classi- fication task assigned each trait into one of three bins (“thinking,” “action,” or “sensation”). In the innateness-rating task, participants indicated “how likely it is that an infant would exhibit this behavior spontaneously, without being shown or taught by a parent, caregiver, or any other person” (1 = very unlikely; 7 = very likely). Results Trait Classification We first confirmed (via mixed-effects logistic regression) that the majority of classification responses were congruent with the intended category (e.g., “thinking,” for cogni- tive traits), and this was the case for both cognitive, M = 0.71, β0 = 1.33, Z = 2.78, SE = 0.48, p = .005, and noncognitive, M = 0.65, β0 = 0.88, Z = 2.15, SE = 0.41, p = .03, traits. Figure 2A plots participants’ ratings for the propensity of cognitive and Innateness Rating noncognitive traits (motor and sensory) to emerge in infants. Noncognitive traits were rated sig- nificantly higher than the scale’s “neutral” midpoint (4), M = 4.67, t1(19) = 4.44, p < .0003, d = 0.99; t2(15) = 3.38, p = .004, d = 0.85, but that was not the case for cognitive traits, M = 3.54, t1(19) = −2.04, p = .055, d = −0.46; t2(15) = −1.78, p = .095, d = −0.45. Critically, cognitive traits were rated as significantly less likely to emerge spontaneously com- pared to noncognitive traits, t1(19) = 5.94, p < .0001, d = 1.27; t2(30) = −3.66, p < .001, d = 0.81. OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science 104 l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . / e d u o p m i / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / i / . 1 0 1 1 6 2 o p m _ a _ 0 0 0 2 9 1 9 2 8 7 9 6 o p m / / i - 0 3 - 1 0 1 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 People’s Intuitions About Innateness Berent et al. Figure 2. The presumed innateness of infant traits (A) and its association with “thinking” response (B). Scatter symbols indicate individual traits. The “thinking”–“innateness” link. We next examined whether the perceived propensity of a trait to emerge spontaneously (a gauge of innateness) is associated with its classification as “thinking” (see Figure 2B). The correlation was negative and highly significant, r(30) = −.793, p < .0001—the stronger the association of the trait with “thinking,” the less likely it was to be viewed as innate. Experiments 3–4: The Innateness of Adult and Infant Traits (Forced Choice) Experiments 1–2 demonstrate that people believe that cognitive traits are less likely to emerge spontaneously relative to noncognitive traits. To further clarify people’s innateness intuitions, in Experiments 3–4, we next asked people to explicitly indicate whether or not these traits are inborn. Experiment 3 featured the adult traits; Experiment 4 presented the infant traits. l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . / e d u o p m i / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / i / . 1 0 1 1 6 2 o p m _ a _ 0 0 0 2 9 1 9 2 8 7 9 6 o p m / / i - 0 3 - 1 0 1 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 Method Experiments 3–4 presented two groups of participants (N = 20 each) with the adult and infant traits from Experiments 1–2, respectively. Participants were asked to make a forced choice as to whether each trait is inborn. Experiment 3 (Adult Traits): Results and Discussion We first compared the mean response for each trait type against chance (.5) using a mixed- effects logistic regression model; another model contrasted responses to cognitive and noncog- nitive traits (with random intercepts by subject and items, and random slopes for trait type by subjects and items). Noncognitive traits were rated significantly higher than chance (M = 0.63, β0 = 0.84, Z = 2.55, SE = 0.33, p = .01, see Figure 3). Cognitive traits, by contrast, were rated reliably lower than chance (M = 0.30, β0 = −1.25, Z = −3.61, SE = 0.35, p < .0004). This result demonstrates that people believe that cognitive traits are not innate. OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science 105 People’s Intuitions About Innateness Berent et al. Figure 3. The presumed innateness of adult traits (A) and its association with “thinking” response (B). In Panel A, scatter symbols indicate the responses of individual participants; in Panel B, they reflect individual traits. A comparison of cognitive and noncognitive traits further confirmed that people were less likely to view cognitive traits as innate than noncognitive traits (β1 = 2.09, Z = 5.75, SE = 0.36, p < .0001). The correlation between the rating of the traits for “innateness” and “thinking” (from Experiment 1) was highly significant, r(78) = −.638, p < .0001. Experiment 4 (Infant Traits): Results and Discussion Responses in Experiment 4 were analyzed as described in Experiment 3. A comparison of the “inborn” responses against chance showed that people believed that cognitive traits are not inborn in infants (M = 0.36, β0 = −0.85, Z = −2.03, SE = 0.42, p = .04), whereas noncognitive traits were considered innate (M = 0.66, β0 = 0.94, Z = 2.55, SE = 0.37, p = .01, see Figure 4). Additionally, cognitive traits were rated as less likely to be inborn relative to noncognitive traits (β1 = 1.78, Z = 4.11, SE = 0.43, p < .0001). The rating of the l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . / e d u o p m i / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / i . / 1 0 1 1 6 2 o p m _ a _ 0 0 0 2 9 1 9 2 8 7 9 6 o p m / / i - 0 3 - 1 0 1 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 Figure 4. The presumed innateness of infant traits (A) and its association with “thinking” response (B). In Panel A, scatter symbols indicate the responses of individual participants; in Panel B, they reflect individual traits. OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science 106 People’s Intuitions About Innateness Berent et al. traits for “innateness” correlated significantly with their rating for “thinking” (from Experiment 2), r(30) = −.761, p < .0001. Experiment 5: Infant Experiments Experiments 3–4 showed that people believe that cognitive traits are unlikely to be innate. It is possible, however, that people are not inherently biased against innate knowledge. Rather, people do not understand how one could evaluate the cognitive capacities of infants, as they are unaware of the experimental methods of infant research. To address this possibility, in Experiment 5, we presented people with detailed vignettes, adapted from four published infant experiments (complete with methods, rationale, and predictions), and elicited a binary yes/no response as to whether those traits are present in newborns. Two of the vignettes clearly captured knowledge. One vignette concerned newborns’ rudimentary numeric cognition—their capacity to match the number of sounds and dots (Izard, Sann, Spelke, & Streri, 2009). A second vignette described infants’ moral preferences—the preference of 3-month-olds for “helpers” over “hinderers” (Hamlin, Wynn, & Bloom, 2010). The third scenario concerned newborns’ preference for syllable structure (e.g., blog>lbog;
Gómez et al., 2014); since this preference could be based on either abstract linguistic knowl-
edge or sensorimotor restrictions, this case was intermediate between cognition and sensation.
The fourth vignette, por el contrario, featured an unambiguous emotional trait—the preference for
happy vs. angry faces (shown in 7-month-old infants, Datyner, Henry, & Richmond, 2017). Si
people are reluctant to view cognitive traits as innate, then they should conclude that infants
are unlikely to exhibit knowledge of number and moral preferences. Emotions, en el otro
mano, will be viewed as innate (Lindquist, Gendron, Oosterwijk, & Barrett, 2013).

Métodos

Twenty participants took part in the experiment. The materials described four published experiments,
examining infants’ sensitivity to four traits: idioma, number, moral preferences, and emotion.
Participants made a binary yes/no response as to whether newborns will be likely to exhibit
sensitivity to the relevant distinction and provided a brief explanation for their response.

Resultados

As predicted, people believed that the two unambiguous cognitive traits—numeric cognition
(m = 0.25, pag = .04) and moral cognition (m = 0.20, pag = .01)—are absent at birth (ver
Cifra 5), and binomial tests indicated that the frequency of these responses differed signif-
icantly from chance. For the language task, responses were at chance (m = 0.45, pag = .82).
Most participants who asserted that newborns prefer syllables like “blog” mentioned the sound
of these syllables in their explanations; this is in line with the possibility that people attribute
syllable structure to sensory, rather than cognitive constraints. A diferencia de, in the emotion task,
people asserted that newborns will show a preference for smiling faces (m = 0.85, pag = .004),
and their justifications often appealed to emotion (p.ej., “I think infants can distinguish between
happy and sad faces”; for all justifications, ver los materiales complementarios; Berent et al., 2019b,
Apéndice 3).

REASONING ABOUT INNATE COGNITIVE TRAITS

Why do people assert that cognitive traits are less likely to be innate? One possibility is that this
belief is due to innocent misinformation. People, en efecto, know that young infants can smile and move,

MENTE ABIERTA: Descubrimientos en ciencia cognitiva

107

yo

D
oh
w
norte
oh
a
d
mi
d

F
r
oh
metro
h

t
t

pag

:
/
/

d
i
r
mi
C
t
.

metro

i
t
.

/

mi
d
tu
oh
pag
metro

i
/

yo

a
r
t
i
C
mi

pag
d

F
/

d
oh

i
/

i

/

.

1
0
1
1
6
2
oh
pag
metro
_
a
_
0
0
0
2
9
1
9
2
8
7
9
6
oh
pag
metro

/

/

i

0
3

1
0
1
pag
d

.

F

b
y
gramo
tu
mi
s
t

t

oh
norte
0
7
S
mi
pag
mi
metro
b
mi
r
2
0
2
3

People’s Intuitions About Innateness

Berent et al.

Cifra 5. The presumed spontaneous emergence of cognitive and emotive traits of newborn
infantes.

but few are aware of research on infant cognition. Respectivamente, participants have no reason to
suspect that some cognitive traits are present at birth. On an alternative account, Participantes'
behavior reflects an active bias. People, in this view, are not simply unaware of innate knowl-
borde. Bastante, they are unwilling to entertain the possibility that some knowledge is innate.

To adjudicate between these possibilities, in Experiments 6–8 we presented people with
detailed vignettes featuring a single trait. Cognitive traits underscored information structure
(p.ej., the rule-based structure of communication), whereas motor traits featured physical ac-
ción. To reduce interference from relevant experience, Experiments 6–7 featured bird and alien
species; Experimento 8 reexamined the basis of the human capacity for language. críticamente, par-
ticipants were provided with evidence indicating that all traits are innate. Of interest is whether
participants would still consider cognitive traits as less likely to emerge spontaneously.

Experimento 6: Bird Traits

Métodos

Participantes

Forty participants took part in this experiment.

The vignettes featured four traits of distinct bird species—two behav-
Materials and Procedure
iors were related to flying, the other two concerned singing. The vignettes were arranged in
matched pairs (ver los materiales complementarios; Berent et al., 2019b, Apéndice 1); one pair
member featured a cognitive trait (p.ej., structure of the swamp sparrow’s song); its matched
member featured a motor trait (p.ej., the quail’s head-bobbing, produced during singing). Par-
ticipants were explicitly informed that researchers believe that each of the four traits are likely
inborn, universal to all members of the species, and early emerging in development. Participe-
pants were next invited to imagine that the bird’s fertilized eggs were incubated in isolation;
the hatched chicks would be well cared for, but without exposure to the behavior at hand.

MENTE ABIERTA: Descubrimientos en ciencia cognitiva

108

yo

D
oh
w
norte
oh
a
d
mi
d

F
r
oh
metro
h

t
t

pag

:
/
/

d
i
r
mi
C
t
.

metro

i
t
.

/

mi
d
tu
oh
pag
metro

i
/

yo

a
r
t
i
C
mi

pag
d

F
/

d
oh

i
/

i

/

.

1
0
1
1
6
2
oh
pag
metro
_
a
_
0
0
0
2
9
1
9
2
8
7
9
6
oh
pag
metro

/

/

i

0
3

1
0
1
pag
d

.

F

b
y
gramo
tu
mi
s
t

t

oh
norte
0
7
S
mi
pag
mi
metro
b
mi
r
2
0
2
3

People’s Intuitions About Innateness

Berent et al.

Cifra 6. The presumed innateness of cognitive and motor traits of birds (in Experiment 6).

They were asked to rate on a 1–7 scale (1 = very unlikely; 7 = very likely) how likely the bird
is to produce the relevant behavior once it matures.

Results and Discussion

Cifra 6 plots participants’ rating of the propensity of bird traits to emerge spontaneously (a
gauge of their perceived innateness). We first confirmed that cognitive, m = 5.74, t(39) = 8.86,
pag < .0001, d = 1.40, and noncognitive, M = 6.13, t(39) = 14.64, p < .0001, d = 2.31, traits were each rated higher than the scale’s “neutral” midpoint. This suggests that people heeded the instructions, indicating that both traits are innate. Of interest, though, is whether they were equally likely to accept these facts in both conditions. partial A 2 Trait (Cognitive/Motor) × 2 Vignette pair ANOVA yielded a reliable effect of Trait, F(1, 39) = 7.05, p = .01; η2 = .153. There was also a marginally significant effect of Vignette pair, F(1, 39) = 4.07, p = .05; η2 = .094, as people gave higher innateness partial ratings to the vignette pair concerning flying compared to those concerning singing. The Trait x Vignette interaction, however, was not significant (F < 1). Thus, despite being explicitly informed that all bird traits are early emerging, adaptive, and likely inborn, people viewed cognitive traits as less likely to emerge spontaneously (relative to noncognitive traits). Experiment 7: Alien Traits Method Participants Twenty participants took part in this experiment. The materials consisted of four vignettes arranged in pairs, matched Materials and Procedure for narrative structure and length. One pair contrasted the cognitive capacity of the alien species to communicate using light signals and their motor capacity for locomotion using a circular movement style. The second pair of vignettes contrasted the cognitive ability of the OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science 109 l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . / e d u o p m i / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / i . / 1 0 1 1 6 2 o p m _ a _ 0 0 0 2 9 1 9 2 8 7 9 6 o p m / / i - 0 3 - 1 0 1 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 People’s Intuitions About Innateness Berent et al. Figure 7. The presumed innateness of cognitive and motor traits in aliens (in Experiment 7). aliens to reckon their navigational path by integrating multiple cues, and their motor capacity for flying by “bounding.” Each such trait was explicitly described as innate, universal, and early emerging in development. Participants were asked to imagine that infant members of the species were reared in isolation (fully cared for) and rate (on a 1–7 scale) how likely each trait is to emerge in those aliens as they grew into adults. Results A comparison of the means against the scale’s “neutral” midpoint confirmed that people thought cognitive, M = 5.10, t(19) = 2.81, p = .01, d = 0.63, and noncognitive, M = 6.03, t(19) = 8.89, p < .0001, d = 1.99, traits would each emerge spontaneously in aliens (see Figure 7). This is only expected given that the instructions explicitly presented both traits as innate. But an inspection of the means suggests that the innateness ratings were nonetheless lower for cognitive traits. A 2 Trait (Cognitive/Motor) x 2 Vignette pair ANOVA yielded a reliable effect of Trait, = .227. No other effects were significant (all F < 1). Thus, F(1, 19) = 5.59, p = .03; η2 people viewed cognitive traits of aliens as less likely to emerge spontaneously. partial Experiment 8: Human Language Methods Participants Forty participants took part in this experiment. The materials consisted of two matched vignettes, describing a re- Materials and Procedure striction on the sequencing of linguistic elements. One story described an abstract cognitive constraint on the syntactic sequencing of actors and actions (e.g., “dogs bark” vs. “bark dogs”); the other story described a motor articulatory constraint on the sequencing of speech sounds OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science 110 l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . / e d u o p m i / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / i . / 1 0 1 1 6 2 o p m _ a _ 0 0 0 2 9 1 9 2 8 7 9 6 o p m / / i - 0 3 - 1 0 1 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 People’s Intuitions About Innateness Berent et al. Figure 8. The presumed innateness of cognitive and motor aspects of human language (in Experiment 8). (e.g., blog vs. lbog). Each such restriction was explicitly described as universal and sponta- neously emerging (without learning). Each story was assigned to a distinct subgroup of partici- pants (N = 20 each). Participants rated (on a 1–7 scale) how likely it is that the restriction will emerge spontaneously among a group of children who are raised together, fully cared for, but devoid of exposure to spoken language. Results Although both traits were presented as innate, participants viewed the cognitive syntactic restriction as significantly less likely to emerge spontaneously than the articulatory motor re- striction on sound combinations, t(38) = 2.12, p = .04, d = 0.67 (see Figure 8). It is unlikely that people simply ignored the instructions. Indeed, cognitive, M = 4.9, t(19) = 2.71, p = .01, d = 0.61, and noncognitive, M = 5.85, t(19) = 6.14, p < .0001, d = 1.37, traits were each rated higher than the scale’s midpoint. Nonetheless, people were reliably less likely to accept the conclusion that syntactic cognitive traits will emerge in humans spontaneously. GENERAL DISCUSSION This investigation evaluated how laypeople reason about the innateness of cognitive traits. Across eight experiments, we found that people consistently consider traits associated with “thinking” as less likely to be inborn. Experiments 1–2 found that people rated cognitive traits as less likely to emerge spon- taneously in both adults and infants. Experiments 3–4 explicitly asked participants whether psychological traits are inborn. To further encourage participants to contrast innate and ac- quired traits, we elicited a forced choice. Here, people responded that noncognitive traits of adults and infants are inborn, but cognitive traits are not. Experiment 5 observed that people were disinclined to believe that infants exhibit certain cognitive traits when they were pre- sented with detailed descriptions of infant research. Finally, Experiments 6–8 presented people with detailed descriptions of various traits of birds, aliens, and humans, suggesting each such OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science 111 l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . / e d u o p m i / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / i . / 1 0 1 1 6 2 o p m _ a _ 0 0 0 2 9 1 9 2 8 7 9 6 o p m / / i - 0 3 - 1 0 1 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 People’s Intuitions About Innateness Berent et al. trait is innate. But despite clear evidence for innateness, people remained less likely to enter- tain the possibility that cognitive traits will emerge spontaneously (i.e., be innate) relative to noncognitive traits. The resistance to innateness was specific to cognitive traits that encompass knowledge. Participants in Experiments 1–4 consistently rated noncognitive traits higher than the scale’s neutral midpoint, but for cognitive traits, they were either neutral (in Experiments 1–2) or ac- tively averse to innateness (in Experiments 3–4). Moreover, the reluctance to view a given trait as innate was negatively correlated with its association with “thinking.” Likewise, participants in Experiment 5 clearly viewed emotions as innate, but they selectively rejected the innateness of numeric and moral cognition. Experiments 6–8 documented the same phenomenon in de- tailed, closely matched vignettes featuring cognitive and motor traits. Whether cognitive traits are in fact innate is a critical question that falls beyond the scope of our research. Our results, however, do suggest that people are reluctant to entertain this possibility. Why are people resistant to the notion of innate knowledge? Our results are not readily explained by previous accounts of antinativism. One such proposal asserts that people are generally resistant to nativism because they are concerned about the social implications of innate individual differences (Pinker, 2002). Another theory suggests that people are blind to nativism because innate mechanisms are incapsulated, and as such, they are opaque to introspection (Carruthers, in press; Cosmides & Tooby, 1994). While these results could offer a partial explanation for our findings, they fail to explain why these biases are selective to innate knowledge, specifically. Another possibility is that participants’ reactions are informed by related life experience suggesting that cognitive traits, such as language and math, are learned. Although this possibil- ity cannot be ruled out, we note that daily experiences also present evidence for the learning of motor skills (e.g., riding a bike, typing, and playing a musical instrument). Additionally, it is unclear why people would maintain this position in the face of explicit information suggesting that the relevant traits are innate, and why they would extend it to a nonhuman (i.e., less famil- iar) species. One could respond by saying that people discount evidence for innate knowledge because they question its reliability; perhaps they assume that cognitive traits are immaterial, so they cannot be measured precisely. Such beliefs, to be sure, are unjustified, as the information presented to participants (in Experiments 6–8) indicates that such traits are innate. Moreover, modern neuroscience tells us all psychological traits—cognitive or not—correspond to phys- ical brain states. So, this explanation begs the question of why people believe that cognitive traits are immaterial, and how this presumption is linked to the bias against innate knowledge. In a fourth explanation, the bias against innate knowledge is at the core of human cog- nition itself (Berent, in press). Past research suggests that people (including young infants) are intuitive Dualists (Bloom, 2004). We view objects as material entities, operating according to the laws of physics (Spelke, 1994; Spelke & Kinzler, 2007), but we attribute the actions of agents to immaterial mental states– their beliefs, knowledge, and goals (Onishi & Baillargeon, 2005; Woodward, 1998). It is precisely because mental states are presumed immaterial that children and adults believe they are more likely to transfer to the afterlife (Bering & Bjorklund, 2004) and migrate from one body to another (Cohen & Barrett, 2008; Cohen, Burdett, Knight, & Barrett, 2011) relative to noncognitive traits. Other results indicate that people are also Essentialists (Gelman, 2003; Keil, 1986). A careful reading of the Essentialism literature further suggests that the essence of living things must be material. It is this presumption that explains why children attribute a doggy’s brown OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science 112 l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . / e d u o p m i / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / i / . 1 0 1 1 6 2 o p m _ a _ 0 0 0 2 9 1 9 2 8 7 9 6 o p m / / i - 0 3 - 1 0 1 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 People’s Intuitions About Innateness Berent et al. color to a tiny piece of matter transmitted from its mother (Springer & Keil, 1991), why they believe that the essence of a fossilized animal resides in a specific physical location (at its center, Newman & Keil, 2008), and why infants expect animate agents to have a material “insides” (Setoh, Wu, Baillargeon, & Gelman, 2013). Discreteness and localization are the defining features of chunks of matter. These two principles of core cognition—Dualism and Essentialism—collide in reasoning about innate knowledge. If cognitive traits are immaterial (per Dualism) and innate traits are material (per Essentialism), then cognitive traits cannot be innate. This proposal explains both why people readily assume the innateness of noncognitive traits and why they are resistant to innate knowledge. Noncognitive traits (sensations, motor traits, and emotions) can be easily mapped to material bodily states, so a mechanism for in- heritance is easy for us to identify. But if, in our eyes, cognition (specifically, knowledge) is immaterial, then it is devoid of the potential for physical inheritance. A bias against innate knowledge, then, could well be the unintended casualty of the collision between two old evo- lutionary forces that shape human reasoning about the physical, psychological, and natural worlds—Dualism and Essentialism. If so, our resistance to innate knowledge could be in our nature. When it comes to knowledge, antinativism could be innate. A series of experiments from our lab is in line with this possibility (Berent et al., 2019a). We found that (a) people consider cognitive traits (from Experiments 1–2) as less material than noncognitive traits (in line with Dualism) and (b) they consider innate traits (i.e., those that define human essence) more material compared to when the same traits are presented as acquired (in line with Essentialism). Moreover, reasoning about innateness can be altered by manipulating Dualism and Essentialism: people become more likely to view cognitive traits as innate when they are prompted to think about minds and bodies as one or the same (in line with Physicalism) compared to situations presenting minds and bodies as distinct (per Dualism). Additionally, when led to believe that the relevant traits are materially represented in the brain (per Essentialism), participants are more likely conclude that the traits are innate (compared to when the traits lack brain instantiation). A second set of experiments (Berent, Feldman Barrett, & Platt, 2019) demonstrate the opposite biases for emotions—traits that are readily linked to the material body. We found that (a) participants assume that emotions are innate and embodied (facially and internally); (b) when told that emotions are localized in the brain (i.e., embodied), people conclude that emotions are innate; and (c) this naïve belief persists even when people are explicitly informed that the emotions in question are in fact acquired. Together, Dualism and Essentialism explain both our negative bias against innate knowledge as well as our positive bias to presume that emotions are innate. Our present results cannot determine why people are resistant to innate knowledge. However, the findings do suggest that people are systematically biased in reasoning about the origins of knowledge. These conclusions shed new light on human nature and suggest caution in the scientific evaluation of innate knowledge. FUNDING INFORMATION This research was supported in part by the Humanities Fellowship (to IB) from Northeastern University. AUTHOR CONTRIBUTIONS IB: Conceptualization: Lead; Formal analysis: Lead; Methodology: Lead; Writing – Original Draft: Lead; Writing – Review & Editing: Lead. MP: Data curation: Supporting; Methodology: OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science 113 l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . / e d u o p m i / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / i . / 1 0 1 1 6 2 o p m _ a _ 0 0 0 2 9 1 9 2 8 7 9 6 o p m / / i - 0 3 - 1 0 1 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3 People’s Intuitions About Innateness Berent et al. Supporting; Writing – Review & Editing: Supporting. GMS: Data curation: Supporting; Writing – Review & Editing: Supporting. REFERENCES Baron-Cohen, S., Leslie, A. M., & Frith, U. (1985). Does the autistic child have a “theory of mind”? Cognition, 21(1), 37–46. doi:10. 1016/0010-0277(85)90022-8 Berent, I. (in press). The blind storyteller: How we reason about hu- man nature. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Berent, I., Feldman Barrett, L., & Platt, M. (2019, September 10). Essentialists biases in reasoning about emotions. Retrieved from http://psyarxiv.com/g92ve Berent, I., Platt, M., & Sandoboe, G. M. (2019a, September 10). How we reason about innateness: The role of Dualism and Essential- ism. Retrieved from http://psyarxiv.com/vy6j5 Berent, I., Platt, M., & Sandoboe, G. M. (2019b). Supplemental mate- rial for “People’s intuitions about innateness.” Open Mind: Discov- eries in Cognitive Science, 3,101–114. doi:10.1162/opmi_a_00029 Bering, J. M., & Bjorklund, D. F. (2004). The natural emergence of reasoning about the afterlife as a developmental regularity. De- velopmental Psychology, 40, 217–233. doi:10.1037/0012-1649. 40.2.217 Bloom, P. (2004). Descartes’ baby: How the science of child devel- opment explains what makes us human. New York, NY: Basic Books. Carruthers, P. (in press). How mindreading might mislead cognitive science. Journal of Consciousness Studies. Cohen, E., & Barrett, J. (2008). When minds migrate: Conceptual- izing spirit possession. Journal of Cognition & Culture, 8(1/2), 23–48. doi:10.1163/156770908X289198 Cohen, E., Burdett, E., Knight, N., & Barrett, (2011). Cross- cultural similarities and differences in person-body reasoning: Experimental evidence from the United Kingdom and Brazilian Amazon. Cognitive Science, 35, 1282–1304. doi:10.1111/j. 1551-6709.2011.01172.x J. Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (1994). Beyond intuition and instinct blind- ness: Toward an evolutionarily rigorous cognitive science. Cog- nition, 50(1), 41–77. doi:10.1016/0010-0277(94)90020-5 Datyner, A., Henry, J. D., & Richmond, J. L. (2017). Rapid facial reac- tions in response to happy and angry expressions in 7-month-old infants. Developmental Psychobiology, 59, 1046–1050. doi:10. 1002/dev.21575 Gelman, S. A. (2003). The essential child: Origins of essentialism in everyday thought. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Gómez, D. M., Berent, I., Benavides-Varela, S., Bion, R. A. H., Cattarossi, L., Nespor, M., & Mehler, J. (2014). Language univer- sals at birth. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 111, 5837–5341. doi:10.1073/pnas.1318261111 Hamlin, J. K., Wynn, K., & Bloom, P. (2010). Three-month- olds show a negativity bias in their social evaluations. Develop- mental Science, 13, 923–929. doi:10.1111/j.1467-7687.2010. 00951.x Izard, V., Sann, C., Spelke, E. S., & Streri, A. (2009). Newborn infants perceive abstract numbers. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 106, 10382–10385. Keil, F. C. (1986). The acquisition of natural kind and artifact term. In W. Demopoulos & A. Marras (Eds.), Language learning and concept acquisition (pp. 133–153). Norwood, NJ: Ablex. Lindquist, K. A., Gendron, M., Oosterwijk, S., & Barrett, L. F. (2013). Do people essentialize emotions? Individual differences in emotion essentialism and emotional experience. Emotion, 13, 629–644. doi:10.1037/a0032283 Newman, G. E., & Keil, F. C. (2008). Where is the essence? Devel- opmental shifts in children’s beliefs about internal features. Child Development, 79, 1344–1356. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8624.2008.01192.x Onishi, K. H., & Baillargeon, R. (2005). Do 15-month-old infants understand false beliefs? Science, 308, 255–258. Pinker, S. (2002). The blank slate: The modern denial of human nature. New York, NY: Viking. Samuels, R. (2004). Innateness in cognitive science. Trends Cogni- tive Sciences, 8(3), 136–141. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2004.01.010 Samuels, R. (2007). Is innateness a confused concept. In P. Carruthers, S. Laurence, & S. Stich (Eds.), The innate mind: Foundations and the future (pp. 17–34). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Setoh, P., Wu, D., Baillargeon, R., & Gelman, R. (2013). Young infants have biological expectations about animals. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 110, 15937–15942. doi:10.1073/pnas.1314075110 Spelke, E. S. (1994). Initial knowledge: Six suggestions. Cognition, 50, 431–445. Spelke, E. S., & Kinzler, K. D. (2007). Core knowledge. Developmen- tal Science, 10, 89–96. Springer, K., & Keil, F. C. (1991). Early differentiation of causal mech- anisms appropriate to biological and nonbiological kinds. Child Development, 62, 767. doi:10.2307/1131176 Wang, J. J., & Feigenson, L. (2019). Is empiricism innate? Preference for nurture over nature in people’s beliefs about the origins of human knowledge. Open Mind. Woodward, A. L. (1998). Infants selectively encode the goal object of an actor’s reach. Cognition, 69(1), 1–34. doi:10.1016/S0010- 0277(98)00058-4 OPEN MIND: Discoveries in Cognitive Science 114 l D o w n o a d e d f r o m h t t p : / / d i r e c t . m i t . / e d u o p m i / l a r t i c e - p d f / d o i / i / . 1 0 1 1 6 2 o p m _ a _ 0 0 0 2 9 1 9 2 8 7 9 6 o p m / / i - 0 3 - 1 0 1 p d . f b y g u e s t t o n 0 7 S e p e m b e r 2 0 2 3INFORME imagen
INFORME imagen
INFORME imagen
INFORME imagen
INFORME imagen
INFORME imagen
INFORME imagen
INFORME imagen
INFORME imagen
INFORME imagen
INFORME imagen

Descargar PDF