Richard Rorty
Philosophy-envy
When philosophers like Ortega y Gas-
set say that we humans have a history
rather than a nature, they are not sug-
gesting that we are blank slates. Ellos
do not doubt that biologists will eventu-
ally pin down the genetic factor in au-
tismo, homosexuality, perfect pitch, luz-
ning calculation, and many other traits
and abilities that differentiate some hu-
mans from others. Nor do they doubt
eso, back in the days when our species
was evolving its way into existence on
the African savannas, certain genes were
weeded out and others preserved. Ellos
can cheerfully agree with scientists like
Steven Pinker that the latter genes ac-
count for various sorts of behavior com-
mon to all human beings, regardless of
acculturation.
What these philosophers doubt is that
either factoring out the role of genes in
making us different from one another, o
Richard Rorty, miembro de la Academia Americana-
mi desde 1983, is professor of comparative litera-
ture and philosophy at Stanford University, como
well as a regular contributor to “The Nation”
and “Dissent.” His books include “Philosophy
and the Mirror of Nature” (1979), “Contingency,
Irony, and Solidarity” (1989), y, más reciente,
“Philosophy and Social Hope” (1999).
© 2004 por la Academia Americana de las Artes
& Ciencias
tracing what we have in common back to
the evolutionary needs of our ancestors,
will give us anything appropriately la-
beled ‘a theory of human nature.’ For
such theories are supposed to be norma-
tive–to provide guidance. They should
tell us what to do with ourselves. Ellos
should explain why some lives are better
for human beings than other lives, y
why some societies are superior to oth-
ers. A theory of human nature should
tell us what sort of people we ought to
convertirse.
Philosophical and religious theories of
human nature flourished because they
stayed clear of empirical details. Ellos
took no chances of being discon½rmed
by events. Plato’s and Aristotle’s theo-
ries about the parts of the soul were of
this sort, and so were Christianity’s the-
ory that we are all children of a loving
God, Kant’s theory that we are phenom-
enal creatures under noumenal com-
mand, and Hobbes’s and Freud’s natu-
ralizing stories about the origins of soci-
ality and of morality. Despite their lack
of predictive power and empirical dis-
con½rmability, such theories were very
useful–not because they were accurate
accounts of what human beings, deep
abajo, really and truly are, but because
they suggested perils to avoid and ideals
to serve. They marketed helpful moral
18
La caída de Dédalo 2004
yo
D
oh
w
norte
oh
a
d
mi
d
F
r
oh
metro
h
t
t
pag
:
/
/
d
i
r
mi
C
t
.
metro
i
t
.
/
mi
d
tu
d
a
mi
d
a
r
t
i
C
mi
–
pag
d
/
yo
F
/
/
/
/
/
1
3
3
4
1
8
1
8
2
8
8
7
6
0
0
1
1
5
2
6
0
4
2
3
6
5
5
3
7
pag
d
.
F
b
y
gramo
tu
mi
s
t
t
oh
norte
0
7
S
mi
pag
mi
metro
b
mi
r
2
0
2
3
and political advice in fancy, disposable,
packaging.
Steven Pinker is trying to recycle this
packaging, wrapping it around a mis-
cellany of empirical facts rather than
around a vision of the good life or of the
good society. But it is hard to see how a
composite, or a synthesis, of the various
empirical disciplines that now call them-
selves cognitive sciences could serve the
purposes that religion and philosophy
once served. The claim that what the
philosophers did a priori and badly can
now be done a posteriori and well by
cognitive scientists will remain empty
rhetoric until its adherents are willing
to stick their necks out. To make good
on the promise of the term ‘a scienti½c
theory of human nature’ they would
have to start offering advice about how
we might become, individually or collec-
activamente, better people. Then they would
have to spell out the inferences that had
led them from particular empirical dis-
coveries about our genes or our brains
to these particular practical recommen-
dations.
mi. oh. wilson, Pinker, and others who
think that biology and cognitive science
can take over at least part of the cultural
role of philosophy are reluctant to start
down this path. They remember the fate
of the eugenics movement–of claims to
have ‘proved scienti½cally’ that interra-
cial marriage, or increased immigration,
would produce cultural degeneration.
Recalling this obnoxious predecessor
makes them leery of betting the prestige
of their disciplines on the outcome of
practical recommendations. En cambio,
they just repeat over and over again that
as we learn more and more about our
genes and our brains, we shall gain a bet-
ter understanding of what we essentially
son.
But for historicist philosophers like
Ortega there is nothing we essentially
son. There are many lessons to be
learned from history, but no super-
lesson to be learned from science, o volver-
ligion, or philosophy. The unfortunate
idea that philosophy could detect the
difference between nature and conven-
tion–between what is essential to being
a human being and what is merely a
product of historical circumstance–was
passed on from Greek philosophy to the
Enlightenment. There it reappeared, en un
version that would have disgusted Plato,
in Rousseau. But in the last two centuries
the notion that beneath all cultural over-
lays there lurks something called human
naturaleza, and that knowledge of this thing
will provide valuable moral or political
guidance, has fallen into deserved disre-
pute.
Dewey was right to mock Plato’s and
Aristotle’s claims that the contemplative
life was the one that best utilized our dis-
tinctively human abilities. Such claims,
he said, were merely ways in which
these philosophers patted themselves
on the back. Ever since Herder, el
Rousseauvian claim that the aim of
sociopolitical change should be to
bring us back to uncorrupted nature
has been rejected by thinkers impressed
by the extent, and the value, of cultural
variación. The idea, shared by Plato and
Rousseau, that there is such a thing as
the good life for man has gradually been
replaced by the conviction that there are
many equally valuable human lives. Este
change has resulted in our present con-
viction that the best sociopolitical setup
is one in which individuals are free to
live whichever of these lives they choose
–to make themselves up as they go
a lo largo de, without asking what they were
somehow ‘meant’ to become. Tiene
also resulted in religion and philosophy
being nudged aside by history, literature,
and the arts as sources of edi½cation and
of ideals.
Philosophy-
envy
yo
D
oh
w
norte
oh
a
d
mi
d
F
r
oh
metro
h
t
t
pag
:
/
/
d
i
r
mi
C
t
.
metro
i
t
.
/
mi
d
tu
d
a
mi
d
a
r
t
i
C
mi
–
pag
d
/
yo
F
/
/
/
/
/
1
3
3
4
1
8
1
8
2
8
8
7
6
0
0
1
1
5
2
6
0
4
2
3
6
5
5
3
7
pag
d
.
F
b
y
gramo
tu
mi
s
t
t
oh
norte
0
7
S
mi
pag
mi
metro
b
mi
r
2
0
2
3
La caída de Dédalo 2004
19
Ricardo
Rorty
en
humano
naturaleza
Carl Degler’s In Search of Human Na-
tura: The Decline and Revival of Darwinism
in American Social Thought tells the story
of the biologists’ attempts to move onto
some of the turf from which the philoso-
phers have been withdrawing. Darwin-
ism revealed previously unsuspected
continuities between humans and
brutes, and these made it seem plau-
sible that further biological research
could tell us something morally sig-
ni½cant. In a chapter called “Why
Did Culture Triumph?” Degler ex-
plains how the overweening preten-
sions of the eugenicists, and the futile
attempt to stem the tide of feminism
by appeals to biological facts about the
differing ‘natures’ of men and women,
helped to discredit this suggestion.
Entonces, in a chapter called “Biology Redi-
vivus,” he describes how sociobiologists
and their allies have been trying to push
the pendulum back in the other direc-
ción.
Degler ends his book on an ecumeni-
cal note, endorsing what Pinker calls
holistic interactionism. But many of his
readers will conclude that the moral of
the story he tells is that “nature or nur-
tura?” was never a very good question.
Darwin did make a tremendous differ-
ence to the way we think about our-
selves, because he discredited religious
and philosophical accounts of a gap be-
tween the truly human and immaterial
part of us and the merely animal and
material part. But nothing Darwin
taught us blurs the distinction between
what we can learn from the results of
biological and psychological experi-
ments and what we can only learn from
history–the record of past intellectual
and social experiments.
Pinker is right that the nature vs. nur-
ture debate will not go away as long as
the question is raised in respect to some
very particular type of human behavior
–autism, Por ejemplo. But at more ab-
stract levels, such debates are vacuous.
They are rhetorical exchanges occa-
sioned by academic turf wars. The ques-
tion “Is our humanity a biological or a
cultural matter?” is as sterile as “Are
our actions determined or do we have
free will?” No concrete result in genet-
circuitos integrados, or physics, or any other empirical
discipline will help us answer either bad
pregunta. We will go right on deliberat-
ing about what to do, and holding each
other responsible for actions, even if we
become convinced that every thought
tenemos, and every move we make, will
have been predicted by an omniscient
neurologist. We will go right on experi-
menting with new lifestyles, new ideas,
and new social institutions, even if we
become convinced that, deep down,
everything somehow depends on our
genetic makeup. Discussion of the na-
ture-nurture question, like discussion
of the problem of free will, has no prag-
matic import.
Pinker says, correctly, that there is a
“widespread desire that the whole
[nature-nurture] issue would somehow
just go away” and an equally widespread
suspicion that to refute a belief in the
blank slate is “to tip over a straw man.”
Readers of Degler will be disposed to
share both that desire and that suspi-
cion. Pinker hopes to change their minds
by tipping over other straw men: “post-
modernism and social constructionism,
which dominate many of the humani-
ties.” But it is hard to think of any hu-
manist–even the most far-out Foucaul-
dian–who would endorse the view, im-
plausibly attributed by Pinker to Louis
Menand, that “biology can provide no
insight into human mind and behavior.”
What Foucault, Menand, and Ortega
doubt is that insights provided by biolo-
gy will ever help us decide which indi-
vidual and social ideals to strive for.
20
La caída de Dédalo 2004
yo
D
oh
w
norte
oh
a
d
mi
d
F
r
oh
metro
h
t
t
pag
:
/
/
d
i
r
mi
C
t
.
metro
i
t
.
/
mi
d
tu
d
a
mi
d
a
r
t
i
C
mi
–
pag
d
/
yo
F
/
/
/
/
/
1
3
3
4
1
8
1
8
2
8
8
7
6
0
0
1
1
5
2
6
0
4
2
3
6
5
5
3
7
pag
d
.
F
b
y
gramo
tu
mi
s
t
t
oh
norte
0
7
S
mi
pag
mi
metro
b
mi
r
2
0
2
3
Philosophy-
envy
Pinker thinks that science may succeed
where philosophy has failed. To make
his case, sin embargo, he has to treat plati-
tudes as gee-whiz scienti½c discoveries.
He says, Por ejemplo, that “cognitive sci-
ence has shown that there must be com-
plex innate mechanisms for learning and
culture to be possible.” Who ever doubt-
ed there were? We already knew, antes
cognitive science came along, that you
cannot teach young nonhuman animals
to do things that you can teach young
humans to do. We ½gured out a long
time ago that if an organism had one
kind of brain we could teach it to talk,
and that if it had another kind we could
no. Yet Pinker writes as if people like
Menand were committed to denying evi-
dent facts such as these.
De nuevo, Pinker cites recent suggestions
that the circle of organisms that are ob-
jects of our moral concern “may be ex-
panded to include people to whom one is
bound by networks of reciprocal trade
and interdependence, y . . . contracted
to exclude people who are seen in de-
grading circumstances.” But we did not
need recent scienti½c research to tell us
about these “possible levers for humane
social change.” The relevance of interde-
pendence to the way we treat foreign
traders, and of degradation to the way
we treat prisoners of war, is hardly news.
People have been recommending trade
and intermarriage as a way of achieving
wider community for a long time now.
For an equally long time, they have been
suggesting that we stop degrading peo-
ple in order to have an excuse for oppres-
sing them. But Pinker describes facts fa-
miliar to Homer and Herodotus as ex-
hibiting “nonobvious aspects of human
nature.”
It is likely that further discoveries
about how our brains work will give us a
lot of useful ideas about how to change
human behavior. But suppose that nan-
otechnology eventually enables us to
trace the transmission of electrical
charges from axon to axon within the
living brain, and to correlate such pro-
cesses with minute variations in behav-
ior. Suppose that we become able to
modify a person’s behavioral disposi-
ciones, in pretty much any way we like,
just by tweaking her brain cells. Cómo
will this ability help us ½gure out what
sort of behavior to encourage and what
sort to discourage–to know how hu-
man beings should live? Yet that sort
of help is just what philosophical the-
ories of human nature claimed to pro-
vide.
Pinker says at various places in The
Blank Slate that everybody has and needs
a theory of human nature, and that em-
pirical scienti½c inquiry is likely to give
us a better theory than either unin-
formed common sense or a priori philos-
ophizing. But it is not clear that we have
or need anything of the sort. Every hu-
man being has convictions about what
matters more and what matters less, y
thus about what counts as a good human
vida. But such convictions need not–and
should not–take the form of a theory of
human nature, or a theory of anything
else. Our convictions about what really
matters are constantly modi½ed by new
experiences–moving from a village to
a city or from one country to another,
meeting new people, and reading new
books. The idea that we deduce them, o
should deduce them, from a theory is a
Platonist fantasy that the West has grad-
ually outgrown.
The books that change our moral
and political convictions include sacred
scriptures, philosophical treatises, intel-
lectual and sociopolitical histories, epic
poems, novels, political manifestoes,
and writings of many other sorts. Pero
scienti½c treatises have become increas-
ingly irrelevant to this process of change.
La caída de Dédalo 2004
21
yo
D
oh
w
norte
oh
a
d
mi
d
F
r
oh
metro
h
t
t
pag
:
/
/
d
i
r
mi
C
t
.
metro
i
t
.
/
mi
d
tu
d
a
mi
d
a
r
t
i
C
mi
–
pag
d
/
yo
F
/
/
/
/
/
1
3
3
4
1
8
1
8
2
8
8
7
6
0
0
1
1
5
2
6
0
4
2
3
6
5
5
3
7
pag
d
.
F
b
y
gramo
tu
mi
s
t
t
oh
norte
0
7
S
mi
pag
mi
metro
b
mi
r
2
0
2
3
Ricardo
Rorty
en
humano
naturaleza
This is because, ever since Galileo, natu-
ral science has won its autonomy and its
richly deserved prestige by telling us
how things work, en vez de, as Aristo-
tle hoped to do, telling us about their in-
trinsic natures.
Post-Galilean science does not tell us
what is really real or really important. Él
has no metaphysical or moral implica-
ciones. En cambio, it enables us to do things
that we had not previously been able to
hacer. When it became empirical and ex-
perimental, it lost both its metaphysical
pretensions and the ability to set new
ends for human beings to strive for. Él
gained the ability to provide new means.
Most scientists are content with this
trade-off. But every so often a scientist
like Pinker tries to have it both ways,
and to suggest that science can provide
empirical evidence to show that some
ends are preferable to others.
Whereas physics-envy is a neurosis
found among those whose disciplines
are accused of being soft, philosophy-
envy is found among those who pride
themselves on the hardness of their dis-
ciplines. The latter think that their supe-
rior rigor quali½es them to take over the
roles previously played by philosophers
and other sorts of humanists–roles such
as critic of culture, moral guide, guard-
ian of rationality, and prophet of the
new utopia. Humanists, such scientists
argue, only have opinions, but scientists
have knowledge. Why not, they ask us,
stop your ears against culture-babble
(which is all you are going to get from
those frivolous postmodernists and irre-
sponsible social constructionists) y
get your self-image from the people who
know what human beings really, truly,
objectively, enduringly, transculturally
son?
Those who succumb to such urgings
are subjected to bait-and-switch tactics.
They think they will learn whether to be
more like Antigone than like Ismene, o
more like Martha than like Mary, o
more like Spinoza than like Baudelaire,
or more like Lenin than like fdr, o
more like Ivan Karamazov than like
Alyosha. They want to know whether
they should throw themselves into cam-
paigns for world government, or against
gay marriage, or for a global minimum
wage, or against the inheritance tax.
They hope for the sort of guidance that
idealistic freshmen still think their
teachers may be able to provide. Cuando
they take courses in cognitive science,
sin embargo, this is not what they get. Ellos
get a better understanding of how their
brains work, but no help in ½guring out
what sort of people to be or what causes
to ½ght for.
This sense that they have been sub-
jected to bait-and-switch tactics often
also afflicts freshmen who sign up for
philosophy courses because they have
been turned on by Marx, Camus, Kier-
kegaard, Nietzsche, or Heidegger. Ellos
imagine that if they take a course in
what are advertised as ‘the core areas
of philosophy’–metaphysics and episte-
mology–they will be better able to an-
swer the questions these authors raised.
But what they get in such courses is, typ-
icamente, a discussion of the place of such
things as knowledge, significado, and value
in a world made up of elementary parti-
cles. Many would-be students of philos-
ophy are unable to see why they need
have views on that topic–why they
need a metaphysics.
It was because Ortega found such top-
ics pro½tless that he wrote polemical
essays like the one from which Pinker
quotes (“History as a System,” in Or-
tega’s Toward a Philosophy of History).
There he said:
22
La caída de Dédalo 2004
yo
D
oh
w
norte
oh
a
d
mi
d
F
r
oh
metro
h
t
t
pag
:
/
/
d
i
r
mi
C
t
.
metro
i
t
.
/
mi
d
tu
d
a
mi
d
a
r
t
i
C
mi
–
pag
d
/
yo
F
/
/
/
/
/
1
3
3
4
1
8
1
8
2
8
8
7
6
0
0
1
1
5
2
6
0
4
2
3
6
5
5
3
7
pag
d
.
F
b
y
gramo
tu
mi
s
t
t
oh
norte
0
7
S
mi
pag
mi
metro
b
mi
r
2
0
2
3
Philosophy-
envy
all the naturalist studies on man’s body
and soul put together have not been of
the slightest use in throwing light on any
of our most strictly human feelings, en
what each individual calls his own life,
that life which, intermingling with others,
forms societies, that in their turn, persist-
En g, make up human destiny. The prodi-
gious achievement of natural science in
the direction of the knowledge of things
contrasts brutally with the collapse of this
same natural science when faced with the
strictly human element.
Ortega insisted that increasing knowl-
edge of how things such as the human
brain and the human genome work will
never help us ½gure out how to envisage
ourselves and what to do with ourselves.
Pinker thinks that he was wrong. But on-
ly a few pages of The Blank Slate grapple
directly with this issue. Among those
that do, the most salient are the ones in
which Pinker argues that scienti½c dis-
coveries give us reason to adopt what he
calls “The Tragic Vision” rather than
“The Utopian Vision” of human life–to
take a dim view of the capacity of human
beings to change themselves into new
and better sorts of people.
In order to show that our choice be-
tween these two visions should be made
by reference to science rather than to
historia, Pinker has to claim, cryptically,
that “parts of these visions” consist of
“general claims about how the mind
works.” But that is just what historicist
philosophers like Ortega doubt. Ellos
think that the contest between these
two visions will be unaffected even if
the brain turns out to work in some
weird way that contemporary science
has not yet envisaged, or if new fossil
evidence shows that the current story
about the evolution of our species is all
wrong. Debates about what to do with
ourselves, they say, swing as free from
disagreements about the nature of neu-
rons or about where we came from as
they do from controversies about the
nature of quarks or about the timing of
the big bang.1
The issue Pinker has with Ortega, y
with most philosophers outside the so-
called analytic tradition, has nothing to
do with blank slates. It is about whether
the conversations among humanists
about alternative self-images and alter-
native ideals would be improved if the
participants knew more about what is
going on in biology and cognitive sci-
ence. Pinker argues that men and wom-
en with moral and political concerns
have always relied upon theories of hu-
man nature, and that empirically based
theories are now available. But Ortega
would reply that for the last few hundred
years we have learned to substitute his-
torical narrative and utopian speculation
for such theories.
This historicist turn does, sin embargo,
owe a great deal to one particular scien-
tist: Darwin. Darwin helped us stop
thinking of ourselves as an animal body
in which something extra, and speci½-
cally human, has been inserted–a mys-
terious ingredient whose nature poses
philosophical problems. His critics said
that he had reduced us to the level of the
beasts, but in fact he let us see imagina-
tive daring as a causal force comparable
to genetic mutation. He reinforced the
historicism of Herder and Hegel by let-
ting us see cultural evolution as on a par
with biological evolution–as equally
capable of creating something radically
new and better. He helped poets like
Tennyson and Whitman, and thinkers
like Nietzsche, h. GRAMO. Wells, George Ber-
nard Shaw, and John Dewey, to dream of
1 For more on this point, see my “The Brain as
Hardware, Culture as Software,” Inquiry 47 (3)
(Junio 2004): 219–235.
La caída de Dédalo 2004
23
yo
D
oh
w
norte
oh
a
d
mi
d
F
r
oh
metro
h
t
t
pag
:
/
/
d
i
r
mi
C
t
.
metro
i
t
.
/
mi
d
tu
d
a
mi
d
a
r
t
i
C
mi
–
pag
d
/
yo
F
/
/
/
/
/
1
3
3
4
1
8
1
8
2
8
8
7
6
0
0
1
1
5
2
6
0
4
2
3
6
5
5
3
7
pag
d
.
F
b
y
gramo
tu
mi
s
t
t
oh
norte
0
7
S
mi
pag
mi
metro
b
mi
r
2
0
2
3
Ricardo
Rorty
en
humano
naturaleza
utopias in which human beings had be-
come as wonderfully different from us
as we are from the Neanderthals. El
dreams of socialists, feminists, and oth-
ers have produced profound changes in
Western social life, and may lead to vast
changes in the life of the species as a
entero. Nothing that natural science tells
us should discourage us from dreaming
further dreams.
yo
D
oh
w
norte
oh
a
d
mi
d
F
r
oh
metro
h
t
t
pag
:
/
/
d
i
r
mi
C
t
.
metro
i
t
.
/
mi
d
tu
d
a
mi
d
a
r
t
i
C
mi
–
pag
d
/
yo
F
/
/
/
/
/
1
3
3
4
1
8
1
8
2
8
8
7
6
0
0
1
1
5
2
6
0
4
2
3
6
5
5
3
7
pag
d
.
F
b
y
gramo
tu
mi
s
t
t
oh
norte
0
7
S
mi
pag
mi
metro
b
mi
r
2
0
2
3
24
La caída de Dédalo 2004
Descargar PDF